table of contents

02/15/2011

Alexander Nehamas on Beauty

Alexander Nehamas received his Ph.D. from Princeton in 1971 and joined the faculty of the philosophy department at Princeton in 1990. He is also Professor of the Humanities and of Comparative Literature. His interests include Greek philosophy, philosophy of art, European philosophy and literary theory. His books include The Art of Living: Socratic Reflections from […]

download transcript [vtt]
00:00:00.000
[Music]
00:00:21.760
This is KZSU Stanford. Welcome to entitled opinions. My name is Joshua
00:00:26.560
Randy and I'm sitting in for Robert Harrison.
00:00:30.640
Mention the word beauty and people tend to go a little overboard.
00:00:35.440
To Iris Murdoch the love of beauty was nothing short of a direct conduit to moral perfection.
00:00:41.120
To John Keats the love of beauty was synonymous with the love of truth.
00:00:45.600
And to the dataists the love of beauty helped bring about the slaughter of millions in World
00:00:49.920
War I.
00:00:51.760
Is the love of beauty the greatest thing we can aspire to then?
00:00:55.200
For the worst calamity ever to before our species.
00:00:58.400
What is the role of beauty in our lives?
00:01:01.200
♪ Praying at disease ♪
00:01:03.200
♪ We're leaving the ones we love ♪
00:01:05.840
♪ And never coming again ♪
00:01:08.000
♪ Long the radio ♪
00:01:10.320
♪ We heard November rain ♪
00:01:12.800
♪ That songs real long ♪
00:01:15.200
♪ But it's a pretty sound ♪
00:01:17.600
♪ We listened to the twice ♪
00:01:19.760
♪ 'Cause the day was asleep ♪
00:01:23.040
(upbeat music)
00:01:25.620
♪ Ba, ba, ba, ba, ba ♪
00:01:28.080
(upbeat music)
00:01:30.120
(upbeat music)
00:01:32.160
It's a little tricky these days to talk about beauty.
00:01:34.720
♪ But beauty can easily seem like a bit of a luxury ♪
00:01:38.400
One we can scarcely afford in a world full of poverty, suffering and violence.
00:01:43.280
It can easily seem like the frivolous pastime of the leasured classes,
00:01:47.120
keeping them closely insulated from the injustices all around them.
00:01:52.000
We're still a fascination with beauty may feel like a form of denial,
00:01:55.920
a way to pretend that all those problems are simply not there.
00:01:58.720
Bertolt Brecht, for example, believe there's a certain kind of art
00:02:03.520
that's just a little too comfortable, just a little too welcoming.
00:02:06.800
It risks making you feel content with the status quo.
00:02:10.880
At the very least, it risks making you feel powerless to change it.
00:02:14.560
There is, of course, still another reason to feel a little suspicious about the love of beauty.
00:02:22.160
The love of beauty involves the making of distinctions, some of which are decidedly invidious.
00:02:27.600
If some things are beautiful after all, then presumably others are not.
00:02:32.560
And as long as we're paying attention to things in the first category,
00:02:36.240
we're going to be paying less attention to things in a second.
00:02:39.280
Take the environment, for example.
00:02:41.440
It's easy to raise money for cuddly pandas and majestic gorillas.
00:02:46.000
But not so easy to get people excited about the Dracula Ant,
00:02:50.400
the Worti-back muscle, and the Dromoduri jumping slug,
00:02:53.920
those unfortunate poor relations of the endangered species family.
00:02:57.680
Needless to say, alas, the same is true for people.
00:03:01.120
Studies repeatedly show that men and women consider attractive,
00:03:04.880
do better in life than men and women not considered attractive.
00:03:08.080
They are, according to some studies, twice as likely to get hired,
00:03:11.920
twice as likely not to get fired, and liable to earn 10 to 15% more than everyone else.
00:03:18.240
The only exception seems to be in jobs like truck driver or security guard,
00:03:22.000
where interestingly enough, women considered attractive,
00:03:24.880
fight it harder to get hired.
00:03:26.160
In certain circles, then beauty has become a bit of a dirty word these days,
00:03:32.080
and some of the criticism is clearly justified.
00:03:34.800
Still, not all of it is.
00:03:37.200
It's true that distinguishing among people on the grounds of their looks is a terrible idea.
00:03:42.320
But distinguishing among artworks on the basis of their aesthetic properties
00:03:47.840
may not be so bad, and distinguishing among times of scenery in this way may be downright important.
00:03:54.320
A study conducted in 2008 showed that quieter, greener, more open spaces
00:04:00.880
significantly reduce the rates of depression in people living in them.
00:04:04.560
There's also some indication that aesthetically pleasing environments may help in reducing crime.
00:04:10.080
And a really fascinating study has shown that when we're in the presence of beauty,
00:04:14.960
looking at a painting we like, for example, our tolerance for pain increases.
00:04:19.920
Good news for dentists.
00:04:21.200
Beauty has its problems then, but it's not all bad.
00:04:25.520
And once more, it's not a luxury either.
00:04:27.920
All of us need to dwell in the presence of beauty, for fear of slowly losing the hope that sustains life.
00:04:34.640
Does that mean Irish modic was right, that beauty is the path to goodness?
00:04:40.880
Try telling that to hell and of trolley.
00:04:43.040
Beauty can just as easily be associated with destructive tendencies as with constructive ones.
00:04:48.000
Does it mean Keats was right, the beauty is the path to truth?
00:04:52.000
Not a chance.
00:04:53.360
Dante's divine comedy is full of egregious errors such as the notion that extramarital
00:04:58.960
sex and homosexuality are mortal sense, or that Brutus and Cassius are two of the three worst
00:05:04.720
people of all time.
00:05:05.520
Yet it's also a poem of great beauty.
00:05:09.600
Does they ask Keats novels make it seem as though criminals are always desperate to confess,
00:05:13.920
and women always desperate to sacrifice themselves to save said criminals,
00:05:17.760
but they're still great works of fiction.
00:05:20.160
And while it's not quite true that all you need is love, it's still a pretty good song.
00:05:25.040
No, beauty is not the path to goodness and it's not the path to truth, but it can, at least,
00:05:32.560
be the path to happiness.
00:05:34.960
A happiness that can coexist perfectly well with the recognition of the world's problems,
00:05:40.000
and with the proper treatment of other human beings.
00:05:42.480
Beauty can be a path to happiness, and it can, in addition, be the path to ourselves.
00:05:49.680
For as proof understood, what we find beautiful is a powerful indicator of who we are at a very
00:05:56.400
deep level.
00:05:57.120
And then again, in the midst of our relentless breakneck rush to achievement,
00:06:02.960
beauty is also there to slow us down, to stop us in our tracks,
00:06:07.440
to create a pregnant silence against the background of which our truest self may once again emerge.
00:06:14.560
My guest today knows a thing or two about beauty.
00:06:20.080
In fact, it's no exaggeration to say he's the world's foremost authority on the subject,
00:06:24.400
having written somewhere between three and five books devoted to it, depending on how
00:06:28.640
I'm on Councilman. His name is Alexander Nehemas. He teaches philosophy and comparative literature
00:06:34.000
at Princeton University, and he's been enormously influential through his long career in a wide
00:06:38.480
variety of fields. He's written a book many consider the definitive study of Nietzsche.
00:06:42.720
He's written books that have reinvigorated the field of Plato's studies. He's settled once
00:06:47.520
and for all what literary scholars call the authorship question, and of course he's written an
00:06:52.080
entire book devoted to the subject of beauty, a book called "Oney, a Promise of Happiness."
00:06:58.080
Alexander, welcome to a entitled opinion. It's a great pleasure to be here with you, Josh.
00:07:02.400
What's really an honor for us to have you here?
00:07:04.240
Alexander, you've written very widely about beauty in many of its aspects. For the sake of
00:07:10.400
today's conversation, I thought it might be helpful to focus on three, the beauty of artworks,
00:07:14.560
the beauty of friends, and the beauty of a human life, but let's start with the beauty of artworks.
00:07:20.960
What about this very widespread tendency on a part of people like Iris Mohr-Dok and others to
00:07:26.720
associate the beauty of artworks with moral improvement? What's your take on that?
00:07:30.480
The idea goes back actually all the way to Plato and the Greeks in general. Ironically, however,
00:07:37.920
we need to remind ourselves that for Plato and the Greeks in general, it wasn't works of art
00:07:44.160
that were the primary objects of beauty. It was human beings. And Plato's discussion generally
00:07:50.480
deals with the beauty of human beings. For him, it was extraordinarily important precisely because
00:07:56.320
he thought that the love of beauty ultimately leads, or in fact is almost identical with, the love of
00:08:03.280
goodness and the love of truth. He established a huge philosophical system around these ideas,
00:08:11.840
a system that actually has seduced or convinced, however you want to look at it. Countless
00:08:17.920
people still then in a sense, a system that we still use today, appeal to today, live within today,
00:08:25.280
if you want, whether we know it or not, scratch the surface of many, many, many above views,
00:08:31.840
and you'll see Plato peeking out on not really peeking out, but standing large behind them.
00:08:40.560
Now, why is it that Plato and others have connected the love of beauty with a love of truth and
00:08:47.760
beauty in goodness? The main idea is I think the following. It's quite obvious to people that goodness
00:08:55.360
and truth are valuable. Now, beauty also seems valuable, but as you were saying in your introductory
00:09:03.600
comments, very often it can be associated with very unpleasant situations. So people try to make a
00:09:11.920
distinction between, so to speak, vulgar beauty on the one hand and true beauty on the other,
00:09:16.800
and accordingly believe that true beauty is distinguished from vulgar beauty or popular beauty,
00:09:23.040
whatever one you call it, precisely because of that connection. Being devoted to beauty,
00:09:29.840
and again, you alluded to that in your comments, very often gives the impression that one is
00:09:36.320
too precious or too, as they say, a state or too rich. Someone who has the luxury of being able to
00:09:44.560
follow in aspects of life that for most people seem to be inaccessible because most people
00:09:51.200
spend most of their lives trying to procure the basic elements to survive, food, small family,
00:10:01.520
some sort of security, whereas it's clear that richer people, richer countries, richer individuals
00:10:09.200
have the leisure and the time to divert themselves to beauty. It seems, I say, because I hope
00:10:13.280
we'll be able to discuss eventually the idea that beauty is not the kind of luxury that it seems to
00:10:19.680
many people to be, but it does look that way. And accordingly, in order to justify it, in order to
00:10:24.720
give it, so to speak, a more serious aspect, people have tried to connect it with truth and beauty,
00:10:30.640
which seem not to need them to justify it. But it was then that leads you to a kind of double bind,
00:10:37.200
because either you seem not to be justifying the pursuit of the beautiful atoll, and it looks
00:10:43.920
useless at worst and damaging, it uses a best in damaging at worst, or you give it a justification
00:10:51.120
in terms of something extrinsed to it like truth, in which case somebody could turn around and say,
00:10:56.400
"But I have a much better way of getting truth. I have science. I have a much better way of making
00:11:02.080
people moral." It's called certain kinds of instruction, at which point do you risk rendering
00:11:07.680
beauty OTO? Do you agree with that? That essentially, justifications of beauty risk this double bind?
00:11:15.440
Absolutely. And one of the ways that the admirers of beauty have tried to counter this
00:11:24.000
submerging or sort of demoting of beauty has been, in my view, something that really doesn't work at
00:11:30.880
all, but nevertheless the procedure is a following. He says, "Well, yes, science is a very, very good
00:11:36.800
truth lead a guy to truth, but not the kind of truth that beauty leads a special kind of truth."
00:11:44.240
Exactly. It's a special kind, and then I think you justify, you sort of confirm the suspicions of,
00:11:51.680
let's call them the anti-beauty crowd, because this special kind of truth that beauty leads to is a
00:11:56.800
truth that only a few people with very special abilities and sensitivities and sensitivities are
00:12:03.200
able to appreciate a very bad kind of a litithm. Exactly. Whereas with science, there's a method by
00:12:09.840
which people can become scientists. We know how do you teach people how to appreciate beauty?
00:12:15.200
Well, you improve their taste, but taste is one of those horrible terms in a way that, again,
00:12:22.000
repeats and replicates all the problems of elitism, difficulty, leisure,
00:12:26.880
aestheticism, and staticism, and so on. So it's a real bind, I think, that people have had,
00:12:32.560
especially when you see that terrible things have been done in the name of the beauty.
00:12:38.320
And then you get into a kind of cynicism that says that beauty is just a mask of evil and injustice,
00:12:46.880
that it's purpose is purely ideological and propagandizing. And I think if you do believe that,
00:12:55.280
you're losing out on an incredibly important aspect of life. In fact, I think that a life without
00:13:02.080
beauty is not a human life. So we could say that the unbeautified life is not worth living,
00:13:08.160
in a way. So somehow we have to find a middle path where we can acknowledge
00:13:14.960
the many propagandistic ideological uses to which beauty is being put on the one hand,
00:13:21.360
and be fully aware of them, straighten the face. But on the other hand, still manage to rescue
00:13:28.320
the parts of beauty that are necessary and maybe even universal. And so maybe not just restricted to
00:13:33.920
this precious, aesthetically. One thing we need to keep in mind is that the assumption, of course,
00:13:41.440
here, is that beauty is at least sometimes a dangerous thing leading to all the bad things that
00:13:49.840
we're talking about. But truth and goodness are not. They're absolutely and always good. But it's
00:13:57.440
easy to show that that's not true about truth, because very often learning that truth can be very,
00:14:04.720
very bad for somebody. Goodness is a bit more difficult, but there have been philosophers,
00:14:11.280
like Nietzsche, who have had their serious doubts about goodness of goodness. So to speak
00:14:17.200
or their value of virtue or the virtue of virtue, if you want. So let's leave that aside for
00:14:21.760
the moment, because I think it complicates matters. Though it's important to keep in mind that
00:14:26.320
nothing really in the world is one way only. And everything has to aspect. Janus is not just the god of
00:14:32.880
the Roman, he's the god of the world altogether. And let's stay with the idea that beauty
00:14:39.760
actually is a dangerous object. It is easy to be seduced by beauty and convinced to do things that
00:14:48.160
you might not do otherwise or you might want to not want to do otherwise and correctly so.
00:14:52.720
So how do we justify it? How do we say it's worthwhile to include beauty in one's life?
00:15:00.320
Well, look, let me play devil's advocate for a moment. And re-advanced a couple of the moralizing
00:15:08.720
position. So there is the Irish Motor position, which I agree goes all the way back to Plato.
00:15:16.160
There's also a more recent position, according to which beautiful objects show a kind of
00:15:23.760
symmetry. So for example, beautiful faces, according to some studies, are beautiful in part
00:15:28.720
because there's a matricle on so on. And so the argument goes, justice is a matter of symmetry.
00:15:35.520
It's a matter of distributing things properly, appropriately, giving the person over here on the
00:15:41.040
left, so to speak, the same as the person over here on the right. Impushingality, impartiality.
00:15:45.120
So according to this argument, encountering beauty, loving beauty predisposes us to being more
00:15:54.560
just and wanting to treat the world as a whole equitably. Another argument, so Kant's argument
00:16:00.960
famously, and particularly in its re-appropriation by Schopenhauer, suggests that maybe we've become
00:16:07.280
hesitate to use the word better people, but maybe we'll say less selfish by virtue of our
00:16:15.200
experiences with the aesthetic, because the aesthetic experiences and experience of disinterested
00:16:20.640
contemplation. So we're looking in our everyday lives, we look at, say, a basket of fruit as
00:16:26.880
something that we want to eat, we want to possess in some kind of way. Whereas if we look at a
00:16:32.000
still life, a basket of fruit, all of a sudden our desires are disengaged. And so again,
00:16:38.960
so here are two arguments, one of which says beauty is all about the symmetrical,
00:16:44.160
and so predisposes us to love the symmetrical and just that's what justice is. And the other
00:16:48.800
argument says beauty is all about being disinterested, it's turning off our desire and being an ethical
00:16:54.400
person is all about turning off our desire. Good, there's a two very complex argument, so let's
00:17:00.160
take them one at a time, let's start with the symmetry. The idea of symmetry again goes all the way
00:17:04.960
back to Plato, Aristotle, and especially Sintergustin, who makes a very, who has a very serious
00:17:10.800
discussion of the connection between beauty and symmetry. Now the trouble in my view is that
00:17:16.400
symmetry is a very peculiar concept. What counts as symmetrical changes with a context.
00:17:25.040
We generally, when we think of symmetry, we think of a purely geometrical or mathematical
00:17:30.240
symmetry, so that if you have three inches on the left of a figure, you have three inches on
00:17:34.560
the right, two inches on top, two inches on the bottom, and that is perfectly fine. If you're
00:17:40.640
interested in having something that exhibits this kind of mathematical geometrical symmetry.
00:17:45.920
And extremely influential in this regard has been the painting of the Renaissance,
00:17:52.720
and generally speaking, representational painting from the Renaissance on, which began, of course,
00:17:59.680
with the fascination of Renaissance paintings with geometry of all things, so that the great
00:18:06.720
paintings of the Renaissance, the Baptism of Christ, or all kinds of other, if you do an analysis of them,
00:18:15.040
you'll see that everything is balanced in the way that we're saying before. But that's not the
00:18:19.360
only axis along which we can be symmetrical. For example, and that's an example I've used before,
00:18:24.480
if you look at a sort of a late middle-aged painter of various Renaissance like Duchyau or
00:18:30.880
a chima bouet. What you see and also isn't in painting, what you see, for example, is that when they do
00:18:36.960
a religious painting, suppose that it's about Madonna and the child, the Madonna and the child are
00:18:42.560
immensely larger than the lay figures or the angels or the saints at us around them.
00:18:48.560
Now that seems perfectly asymmetrical from a later Renaissance point of view, but in fact,
00:18:54.240
what they are trying to suggest is not so much the arrangement of the figures in the painting,
00:19:00.240
but the importance of the figures in the painting. So it is symmetrical to have a larger
00:19:05.040
version, Mary, than a saint or in particular a lay, a sort of a mortal person, because that's what
00:19:12.240
you're measuring it. So to say that beauty is symmetry, maybe correct if we think that symmetry does
00:19:19.680
not specify a specific feature. If it does specify a specific feature, then it'll turn out that many
00:19:25.120
things that we consider beautiful will turn out to be not beautiful by that argument. Maybe another
00:19:30.480
way of saying this would be to say that in fact not all things that we consider beautiful exhibit
00:19:37.760
that kind of symmetry. I mean, maybe it's something more like harmony in which, so to take your
00:19:44.240
example of these paintings, maybe one shouldn't say that there's supposed to be a symmetry
00:19:51.200
between the Virgin Mary and the other figures. But they're supposed to rather to be an asymmetry
00:19:55.840
between them, which then comes together in a greater harmony. Here's another example, if you don't
00:20:01.840
like this one, I have the formé reproduction of Magritt's The Traveler from 1937, one of my
00:20:07.920
figures. Magritt's a very striking and weird image in which you have some kind of odd floating balls
00:20:17.440
floating above the sea, maybe a little meteor or planetoid or something, which seems to be made up of an
00:20:24.800
armchair and torso, sculpture, and a lion and a tuba and some other stuff. And one doesn't want to
00:20:34.480
say, I assume that somehow the tuba and the armchair and some symmetrical relationship with each
00:20:43.040
other, but there might be some kind of harmony, some kind of quasi musical chord that's produced
00:20:51.200
out of them. If that's the case, then maybe we should hesitate before applying this to the world in
00:20:57.760
front of us, before trying to legislate on the basis of this, or act morally on the basis of this,
00:21:04.000
because that might lead to disastrous results in which you think, for example, it would produce a
00:21:08.640
beautiful harmony if we had certain people with red hair treated very differently, people with dark hair.
00:21:15.440
Sure. Actually, I think that we could say that beauty is connected or even if we don't identical with
00:21:21.280
symmetry, if we realize that symmetry changes depending on the context, and that thing the same
00:21:26.960
thing could be said about harmony in a way, because what counts as harmonious in one situation
00:21:31.760
is not harmonious in another. And that's a trouble with taking a specific expression of symmetry
00:21:37.280
or harmony and saying that's the way to go. Yes, lots of modern music is not harmonious by
00:21:44.560
baroque standards, but that doesn't mean that all of it is ugly or indifferent or whatever.
00:21:50.880
I want to say something else about symmetry, and because you started out with saying that
00:21:55.200
symmetrical faces are judged beautiful, and that's in a sense very true. There's a series of
00:22:01.520
experiments, many, many experiments, where you show people photographs of faces and ask them to
00:22:08.240
judge them for attractiveness or beauty or something like that. Well, it turns out that they can
00:22:12.960
digitize their photographs, and the more photographs of different faces you superimpose on each other,
00:22:19.840
the more people that tend to agree on who is attractive and who isn't. If you show them, say,
00:22:25.360
eight individual pictures, each one of one face, people will have all kinds of different views.
00:22:30.640
Show them each one being true, it compons it. Yeah, there's more agreement for, more,
00:22:36.560
eight, even more, and so on and so forth. And it turns out, of course, that the more faces you superimpose
00:22:41.360
upon on another, the more average the face becomes. Averageness is attractive. Averageness is
00:22:46.560
attractive. Why? Because average is symmetrical. Right. And why is symmetry attractive? Well,
00:22:53.600
here, evolutionary psychologists come in and they say, "symmetry is health," because if one part of
00:22:59.760
the body or the face grows at a different speed than another, it shows that something was wrong.
00:23:06.720
And so what we look for is health, the namely reproductive fitness, and that's what beauty really is.
00:23:14.000
I think much as I agree with the basic conclusions that they reach about, when is it that people
00:23:21.120
agree about beauty, I think the inference that that's what really, that's beauty really is.
00:23:26.080
Namely, simply, reproductive fitness is absolutely unjustified by the conclusion.
00:23:31.760
To ask you to judge whether something is attractive or not, or especially a person is attractive or
00:23:40.160
not, on the basis of a photograph of usually an expressionless face, is like the following.
00:23:47.840
You, I know, like a resort, correct. Right. So I feed you your favorite resort. And then I
00:23:57.600
shut you up in a room where I don't feed you anything for 30 days or so. After 30 days,
00:24:04.800
you will eat just about anything. That doesn't mean that what you really like to eat is the
00:24:09.920
cockroach that was running around yourself and that the resort is just something that you'll have
00:24:16.240
if and only if you have the chance to eat it and that what human beings really like to eat is cockroach.
00:24:22.640
What it shows is that in extremely outlying situations, extremely unusual situations,
00:24:28.160
we resort to our most basic instincts and abilities. Right. So if you're seeing, if you're supposed to
00:24:34.000
judge a person from this expressionless photograph, it's quite likely that you will fall back to your
00:24:39.120
most primitive abilities. But your most primitive abilities are not the abilities that are
00:24:45.040
exhibited when you're in a normal situation. And the idea that they represent the core, the essence of
00:24:50.800
reality of our attitudes is I think very, very wrong one. What we're showing is that those
00:24:55.760
abilities express themselves when we are in totally unusual situations from the total ones.
00:25:01.680
When I judge a person's beauty, I don't, I look at their movement. I look at their expressions.
00:25:09.200
It takes time. I don't do it instantaneously the way that these experiments presuppose.
00:25:14.000
And I judge the whole person, not just the face. Right. So it's a very different approach.
00:25:19.520
And explains perfectly well where some of the most beautiful people are also highly asymmetrical indeed.
00:25:25.360
Which is a bit of a problem for that. Well, what they try to say is that well, it turns out that
00:25:30.800
a beauty is not the only thing that matters. There's also kindness and intelligence and interest.
00:25:35.920
But they have what I would call a layer cake view of the person. There's the fundamental beauty and
00:25:41.040
then there's something else called intelligence, something else called kindness and something else called
00:25:44.880
sensitivity. And so I don't think that's true at all because I think that when we judge somebody's
00:25:49.440
beauty, we involve all these things at the same time. If somebody's intelligent, we see it in their
00:25:55.600
face and their faces animated by them intelligence and accordingly, more beautiful. That's right.
00:26:01.680
And the converse. And exactly in the converse. That's very interesting. I mean, well, for many reasons,
00:26:06.880
partly because it seems to know what you were saying in your risotto remarks is a kind of overturning
00:26:13.680
of the kind of criticism we were mentioning earlier about elitism, east-feet, preciousness.
00:26:21.840
Because it seems to me that what you're saying is that in fact, that's the default case.
00:26:27.600
The default case is that we human beings pay attention to beauty around us. We human beings
00:26:35.120
value beauty around us. And it's only under extreme circumstances that we don't. I wonder if this
00:26:40.160
goes along with some of the work that Ellen DeSoneiake has done in which she's shown that across the world,
00:26:49.920
any culture that we know anything about, there's always something that she calls making special.
00:26:55.360
Absolutely. There's always an activity we would call aesthetic. That makes it sound too narrow.
00:27:00.800
So she's quite rightly used as the term making special. They're always
00:27:04.400
certain objects, for example. They're singled out, sometimes for devotional uses, and they're heavily
00:27:09.920
decorated. So it seems as though everywhere you turn, human beings are engaged in separating out
00:27:17.360
one kind of thing from another kind of thing. In ways that we Westerners would associate with
00:27:23.600
making a distinction between more beautiful and less beautiful.
00:27:26.080
I'm really at my deSoneiake as well. I don't at my the fact that she tries to use that
00:27:34.320
extraordinary interesting research to bash what she calls postmodernism. I think that very little
00:27:40.640
follows from evolutionary psychology about specific art forms. There's a recent book by Dennis
00:27:48.000
Dutton who tries to do similar things that I think really don't work at all that way. Much as
00:27:54.240
the original research may be interesting. The specific way of the specific strategy of using that
00:27:59.840
that's up to bash or to support certain particular artistic movements or whatever that doesn't work.
00:28:05.120
But the idea of making special I think is extremely, extremely important and interesting.
00:28:09.440
Whenever we see objects that have a very common form, we will always find some features that
00:28:19.360
differentiate one from the other. What are those features do? Those features give the object
00:28:26.640
a character, an individuality if you want, that allows us to say it stands out from the rest or not
00:28:33.680
to say that, but when we look at a whole bunch of pots that say ancient Athenians made,
00:28:40.160
there are some that stand out. We say, "Ah, look at that one." And to a very great extent,
00:28:46.400
I think that beauty can be associated with distinction in both senses of the term in a way.
00:28:54.960
But you see how important that is on a very basic elementary sort of bio-psychological case,
00:29:01.040
it allows us to focus attention. Now, and he comes to a whole notion of taste that we're saying before,
00:29:07.360
people are likely to focus on different things. With the vase or the pot that you choose need not
00:29:15.280
be the pot that I choose, nevertheless, we each choose the pot that we choose because we see in it
00:29:22.480
something that we don't see in other things, and very interestingly, something that other people don't see in it.
00:29:30.080
In so far as I see something in the object that other things don't have, and that other people don't see,
00:29:40.240
I become distinct from the other people, you see. And the idea of focusing on beauty and focusing
00:29:50.400
distinction in the sense reflects back on the person who's doing the focusing and makes that particular
00:29:56.560
person distinct in a similar way, which goes back exactly to what you said about what you mentioned
00:30:02.160
in connection with proof before that in focusing on beauty we reveal our deepest self.
00:30:09.040
You're listening to KZSU Stanford, I'm Joshua Landy, sitting in Robert Harrison,
00:30:14.000
and I'm talking with Alexander Nahamas, Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University about the
00:30:18.320
beauty of artworks, friendship, and lives. We're in the middle of talking about the value of beauty.
00:30:24.560
I think we've reasonably dismissed the Keats claim that it's all about truth and also the
00:30:30.800
Murdoch slash, if not dismissed, at least put them aside for the moment.
00:30:35.280
We'll put aside for the moment. The very important challenges from those who want to connect to
00:30:40.800
the truth and those who want to connect it. With the moral, maybe if we have time we can come back to
00:30:45.920
KANS objection, but let's pursue this idea that you just brought up that
00:30:50.320
one of the important effects for our life of engaging with beautiful objects and people
00:30:58.720
is that it somehow brings out our own distinctness. Can you say a little bit more about that?
00:31:09.120
What do the things that you like that you love, say, which is even more appropriate, I think in
00:31:16.640
this question, what are the things that you find beautiful? What do the things that you find beautiful
00:31:20.720
show about yourself? Well, let's put it that way. I go to the museum.
00:31:28.240
Actually, let me give you an actual example. I was at the opera, some years ago, and I was watching
00:31:38.640
the Strauss opera, the woman without chatter. At the end, of course, this is a very peculiar
00:31:46.640
opera. It involves spirits and human beings and interactions between the two and all that. It's a
00:31:52.800
kind of weird, actually weird story. At the end of the show, of the opera, the king, one of the
00:32:01.440
characters, sings something to the audience saying, "If you look carefully, if you look closely,
00:32:08.720
you will see that all these things are humans and that we're all brothers, something like that."
00:32:12.960
The staging of the opera at that point did the following. It took the set away. It showed all
00:32:22.000
these stage mechanisms that were behind this, all the lighting and the pulleys and the
00:32:29.280
various machines that they have to use. It also raised the lights in the house. All of a sudden,
00:32:36.480
you realize that this artistic creation that tells you that the content of it is all human,
00:32:45.120
is also produced only by humans and that the characters on the stage, this stage hands and the
00:32:53.200
machines that made the illusion possible and the audience that is observing it are all on the same
00:32:59.120
level. That's a brilliant, absolutely brilliant, cool. What did I say about you?
00:33:06.080
Where does this make you distinct? But there are a lover of this kind. But first, before we go to that,
00:33:12.320
what did I want to do when I felt that? I want to tell people about it.
00:33:16.480
It's not that I just said, "Oh, it's wonderful and I'm going to sit here and one low in it."
00:33:23.120
I wanted to discuss it and I wanted some at least of my friends to agree with me, not all of them
00:33:29.760
because I have friends who don't like opera and who think that it's ridiculous that I even
00:33:34.960
pay money to go see such things. But I wanted to now. Why is it important that I wanted to
00:33:41.360
tell those friends that might even enjoy risotto? Well, then they may not be such good things.
00:33:50.000
I take that. So why did I want to talk about it? Because when I judge at something
00:33:56.080
is beautiful, I find something beautiful. I am not simply saying I like it. I'm saying it's
00:34:02.560
something that others ought in some sense of another of ought, ought to find beautiful.
00:34:08.800
Now that's where Kant may come into the picture of it because Kant noticed this fact about it,
00:34:16.000
but he thought that the ought applies to absolutely everyone. So he thought that when you say that
00:34:22.640
something is beautiful, although that's not, and we no need to go into that, an objective judgment,
00:34:27.040
the way that say the judgment is wet. Let's see. Well, I'm not sure about that.
00:34:31.360
The she's water is water wet. Another question, a platonic question. If you went to it,
00:34:38.480
if you say the table is brown or any other seas wet for that matter could be either right or
00:34:44.640
wrong after all, if correct, everyone should in fact agree with you that the table is brown.
00:34:50.640
It's clear to me that that doesn't happen with beauty. Right. Kant thought that that's
00:34:56.960
if he thought that was due to very different reasons, but it's not that ideally everybody should
00:35:02.240
agree. I don't think so. Because we don't say this is beautiful for me. Exactly. Exactly.
00:35:07.200
I find this beautiful in the way that we say his famous example is Canary wine.
00:35:10.880
Canary wine can every way unpleasant, but you may not. We don't say that about things we find
00:35:15.920
beautiful. So it's a subjective judgment that nonetheless commands according to him a certain kind
00:35:20.880
of universality of agreement. Yeah, a universal agreement. I think that he's right about the fact
00:35:25.760
that it's not like Canary wine or the traditional philosophical modern ice cream. I say strawberry
00:35:31.760
or vanilla. I think depends on your taste. I think it applies to a smaller group of people.
00:35:39.760
And I think that explains a phenomenon that in fact people, some people agree about some things and
00:35:45.120
they disagree about others. And yet, there's other people who agree with them about these
00:35:48.480
agree about still others and so on. In other words, I think that when you say that something is
00:35:53.600
beautiful, you're envisaging a community, which will not necessarily be incomplete agreement about it
00:36:00.400
and very often will not even agree on the reasons why the object is beautiful, but will engage with
00:36:07.520
you on the assumption that the object is. What's very interesting about this kind of this approach to
00:36:13.840
the sort of the universality or the generality of beauty is that it allows us to explain why it is
00:36:22.400
that very often I can disagree with somebody about a judgment of beauty and yet not think that I
00:36:27.200
need to change a mind about it. The classic example, of course, is the following.
00:36:34.800
We Westerners by and large think that Rembrandt is a great painter. Now, it's quite clear that somebody
00:36:41.440
living in the northwest of China has never heard of Rembrandt and probably would not know what to make
00:36:47.200
of a Rembrandt self-portrait if he or she ever saw it. Now, should we convince that person that they
00:36:54.720
should like Rembrandt? Well, there's one sense in which we could say yes, why not. There's another sense
00:37:02.160
though in which when you think about it, you see, it's not as simple as that. You can't take somebody
00:37:06.880
like that and introduce them to Rembrandt. In order for them to like, so to speak, Rembrandt,
00:37:13.360
they have to be socialized into Western culture in general. And it's not at all clear to me
00:37:19.760
that it's always a good thing for somebody to be. So it's not clear to me that their life is going
00:37:25.200
to be necessarily better if they become a Western museum goer than if they are whatever it is that they
00:37:32.080
are at a time. So differences in social, intellectual, economic, even psychological makeup, I think,
00:37:41.200
justify aesthetic disagreements that don't involve trying to convince the others. And my
00:37:47.920
way of thinking about that has to do, my model is ancient Greek religion, polytheism, where you
00:37:56.640
are a follower of Aphrodite and you're a follower of Apollo. Exactly. Artemis, say, that's a better
00:38:02.480
country. That's a better country. I don't know who should be who. And we can recognize each other
00:38:09.520
as religious. We are both religious, but there's no sense of obligation that I need to convince you
00:38:16.480
that you should have Artemis or Aphrodite and you conversely. And yet, isn't there something
00:38:21.680
there's a strange phenomenon that happens when somebody you know and love turns out to have a radically
00:38:30.240
different reaction to something. So linear Anderson is one of my favorite people in the entire world.
00:38:34.480
He and I went to see a film called Next.Wanderland. Have you been subjected to this?
00:38:39.200
Subjective. Well, then, the same line to you. We sat through this film. That's the
00:38:45.680
verb I would use. And then at the end, I was thinking thank goodness. Now we can rush out and start making
00:38:53.440
fun of this film. But no, linear was sitting there through all of the credits deeply moved by
00:38:59.040
the entire experience. And the converse happened. This was a plumber, right? Yes, in Boston. Yes,
00:39:04.000
yes. Yeah, I'm kind of horrified at how well you remember this film. Then the converse, of course,
00:39:09.600
happened with Charlie Kaufman's adaptation, which is one of my favorite films and linear
00:39:13.600
things is that's one of the old audiences with the orchestra and Floyd adaptation of Susan or
00:39:19.040
Lean's. Yeah, or anything. And that's, you know, those situations are very interesting because obviously
00:39:25.120
you're not going to fall out over this. And you're not going to think the other person is
00:39:33.600
somehow wicked as if they committed a crime. And yet, you wonder whether you really know that.
00:39:41.200
So I guess what I'm curious about is what's the function of these micro communities? What do you
00:39:45.440
do for us? And what does it mean for us if it turns out that we, you know, I and some other person
00:39:53.120
don't belong quite the same micro we never belong completed to any micro community. That's part
00:39:59.200
of the point. It's that they're always going to be differences. Thank goodness because if there
00:40:04.400
weren't differences that way, we would become carbon copies of one another. And that's exactly what
00:40:09.840
at least we in the West think and I think everybody actually does as well. We shouldn't, we shouldn't be,
00:40:15.760
we should not, we're not ants. And I think the idea that everyone would have the same taste ultimately
00:40:22.720
reduces to the ant colony. Now that's of course an exaggeration, but this is where the idea
00:40:29.440
tends now about about your disagreements. There is a kind of disappointment. One of my best
00:40:36.400
friends for example, who is in fact a great opera lover doesn't like proves and it is a very
00:40:42.800
that's shocking. It's actually an immoral. But you know, I can live with it because I can see
00:40:51.600
how it fits with other things about him. And I can also live with it because I know that
00:40:57.520
there isn't a single right way to be at the same time. And I think you're absolutely right about
00:41:03.440
that. There is a sense that you realize I don't know that person exactly as I thought I did,
00:41:08.960
but that's okay too. There is no reason that we should know everyone as deeply as all that
00:41:15.360
shows to predict their taste. In fact, if you can predict somebody's taste, namely if you assume
00:41:20.080
that they will like exactly what you would like and for the same reasons, then you've reduced them to
00:41:25.360
an non-human being anymore. They're now going to have an algorithm. They can use, I mean,
00:41:32.320
they're a clone or a computer or whatever it is. By the same token, you can be deeply disappointed
00:41:40.640
if a friend of yours, but seriously is appointed. And in some cases, you can consider aesthetic
00:41:46.880
disagreements as fatal to a relation. I'll give you two examples. Not from fiction, one from
00:41:55.600
reality. The fictional one is the play by Jasmine Reza Art, where one of the three friends buys
00:42:03.440
a minimalist white painting and the other friend thinks it's a ridiculous thing. And they start
00:42:09.280
having arguments about it. At one point, the fellow who doesn't like the painting says,
00:42:15.440
"I could not love Sairz," let's see, man's name. "I couldn't love Sairz, who loves this painting?"
00:42:22.320
You see, because what he thinks it shows about Sairz is something very deeply wrong with him.
00:42:27.440
And the friendship begins to unravel in every which way they end up hating each other's
00:42:33.600
taste in food, each other's taste in women and so on and so forth. Now, fortunately, the story I'm
00:42:39.440
going to tell you did not have the same end, but a friend of mine who many, many years ago,
00:42:44.560
moved from an intellectual academic background to a business background in Palo Alto, as a matter of fact,
00:42:51.920
I started working there and I went to visit a year later and I arrived there and I saw that this man
00:42:59.680
was completely immersed in what I would call a kind of business culture. Money, cars,
00:43:08.960
vacations and one night we're having dinner. We're having some tension about that. And one night
00:43:16.080
at dinner, we're as restaurant together and there was a picture on the wall. And he said,
00:43:20.080
"I don't understand why anybody bothers with originals. What's the point about originals? If you
00:43:24.960
have a copy that looks the same, then it says good as the original." And at that point, I felt that
00:43:32.080
we had drawn so far apart that our friendship would not survive. And in fact, I left early,
00:43:38.560
I went back and fortunately the whole thing worked out perfectly well in the end and
00:43:42.240
I guess that doesn't fit perfectly what I said before, but he ended up agreeing with me.
00:43:50.000
But this is where you realize that sometimes aesthetic differences express really fundamental differences.
00:43:56.240
So maybe we can summarize by saying the following. First of all, there can be such a thing as bad taste,
00:44:06.320
which is not to say that there's a universal standard of taste. Everyone should like the same things,
00:44:14.800
but there could be a case in which your various tastes don't hang together as you would just say.
00:44:21.920
And that can be a mark of it. You somehow haven't done the work required to put your soul
00:44:28.320
in order so that you would... Well, nice to put. So that's one thing one could say. A second thing
00:44:33.760
one could say is, "A version of the Christian point, your friend had changed and his change nature
00:44:40.560
was expressed in his aesthetic taste." Exactly. And so we can actually infer things about the people
00:44:48.080
that we know and care about on the basis and we can know things about ourselves, in fact,
00:44:52.880
on the basis of the kinds of things we find beautiful and cherished. But you can't always
00:44:58.080
infer things especially about people you don't know from their taste. You need to understand
00:45:03.600
how things, if and how things hang together before you can make the judgment. I like the way you're
00:45:10.080
saying it earlier, you have to understand how this aesthetic judgment hangs together with the rest
00:45:15.520
of what you know about them. You don't just take it in isolation. And to some extent, I think that
00:45:21.200
a lot of people who pay a lot of attention to aesthetics and beauty tend often to make,
00:45:26.320
so to speak, ethical judgments about in bi-ethical, I mean, just judgment about how good they are,
00:45:32.320
not just necessarily, but in every other way. Simply by looking... Well, they like football.
00:45:39.280
I like opera. So, they're terrible people. They're low-class or whatever it is. And it turns out, of
00:45:45.600
course, that could be right, that generally isn't. And there's much more to it than that. In other
00:45:52.320
words, it's not... it's important not to rush to judgment in cases like that. We generally think
00:46:01.760
that aesthetics and the rush to judgment go together, because many people think that, well, you look
00:46:07.280
at something beautiful, or hear something beautiful, and there it is. You've got it all.
00:46:10.560
Whereas I really think, and that may be an intellectual approach in a way, but...
00:46:16.000
Well, can I say that understanding and appreciating and loving the beauty of something
00:46:23.920
always involves you into trying to understand it better. And accordingly, beauty is a property,
00:46:31.040
so to speak, of objects, that appears and is sort of, speak, deployed over time. Of course,
00:46:39.520
there is that magic moment of love at first sight and all that, but it's a bit more complicated than
00:46:45.040
that. And that could be love at first sight, but love that first sight that lasts for 10 years,
00:46:50.880
is not the same thing. It really develops, gets complicated, applies to other aspects of your life,
00:46:58.240
and so on. And I think that that's where one can and should return to Plato, and say that love and
00:47:05.200
knowledge are not completely separate at all, that to love something is essentially also involves
00:47:12.880
the effort to come to know it better. Now, I don't think that knowledge necessarily makes you
00:47:18.880
more, more person, either. So the idea is that even... I know you're claiming I take it. This is the
00:47:27.360
avenue to truth, generally speaking. No, absolutely. You're talking about it as the knowledge of the
00:47:32.320
artwork. Of course, knowledge of the artwork often involves other things as well, because what is it
00:47:39.200
to understand something, to understand something, in my view, is to try to establish exactly what it is,
00:47:46.800
and how, like the ports that we're talking about before, it differs from the other ports.
00:47:52.400
So in order to understand it, you need to see how it is similar to a different from all the other
00:47:59.040
things of its kind. So in order to understand this, to understand exactly this port, you need to
00:48:05.680
understand ports. Alexander, we're coming towards the end of our first hour together.
00:48:11.760
Listeners may... I hope we have. We did know that we have another hour of conversation coming.
00:48:21.360
And let's return in that other hour to these questions about coming to know the artwork and
00:48:26.560
distinguishing it from other things. And also to the vital question of what it is that these
00:48:32.160
artworks do for us, these unpredictable bonus they confer upon our lives. But I want to return
00:48:38.240
briefly to something you were saying earlier about certain kinds of unfortunate judgments against,
00:48:47.280
for example, people who enjoy watching football. I'm hoping that by football you mean soccer,
00:48:52.080
in which case I'm fully included in that category.
00:48:55.840
Well, I didn't at the time, but I wouldn't have any kind of contempt for people who like what
00:49:02.560
people will soccer. I don't have a contempt either for people who like football either, but yes,
00:49:08.640
I was wonderful. Yeah. This was just a pretext for me to get you to talk about television,
00:49:15.200
because I know that you've written very eloquently about television.
00:49:19.360
You've confessed to being a fan of Frazier, which I find inexplicable, but...
00:49:25.840
Well, you also didn't like Wonderland, so... Yes, this is a good point.
00:49:28.960
Could you say something a bit about that? I mean, I have two questions about one of which is,
00:49:34.400
what should one say in defense of television? Obviously, television is eminently
00:49:41.760
defendable, but at the same time it clearly needs a defense against certain kinds of critique.
00:49:47.120
And secondly, how on earth does your love of television, a passionate love of television,
00:49:50.880
which has even had you writing articles about television go along with your love of opera?
00:49:54.640
Well, I mean, are you supposed to be coherent in your tastes, too?
00:49:58.880
Yes, but it takes a while to see it.
00:50:00.640
Now, what was your first question?
00:50:05.120
How should we defend television?
00:50:07.520
Well, defend television.
00:50:09.120
And indeed, I mean, one of the things I love about your work is that you haven't merely defended it.
00:50:12.800
You even explain how in some contexts it's superior as a media.
00:50:16.640
There are certain things that television can do that other media can't.
00:50:19.760
Well, actually, I think it's not right to speak of defending television.
00:50:24.720
Could I defend writing?
00:50:27.200
There is a myth by Isop where the Master Sense Isop to the market,
00:50:35.200
and he says, "Bring me the best thing that they have in the market."
00:50:39.440
And Isop brings his Master a tongue.
00:50:44.880
And he says, "Pant-wise, what's better than the tongue? Aren't the greatest achievements of people
00:50:50.640
established by speech and so on and so forth?" And he says, "Okay, now go bring me the worst thing."
00:50:56.480
And he comes back with the tongue.
00:50:57.680
And you see where this is going.
00:51:00.720
So, the same thing with writing, some of the worst things in the world have happened because of
00:51:05.360
writing and some of the very best things in the world.
00:51:07.360
So, it's not a medium is not to be defended in itself.
00:51:12.320
A medium, and that applies also to genres, I think.
00:51:16.240
A medium or a genre is to be defended for the good things that it does,
00:51:20.960
because it's always possible to do something terrible.
00:51:23.520
The genre, as we're saying before, nothing is absolutely one way or the other.
00:51:29.120
So, when I try to, so to speak, defend television, what I like to try to do is to say,
00:51:35.840
look, very many criticism of television as a medium.
00:51:39.520
Proceed from the fact that people take the achievements of another medium
00:51:45.600
that they are used to, that they consider pedagmatic, and apply them to television,
00:51:51.200
or to any other medium for that matter.
00:51:53.040
And since, of course, media can accomplish different things and say,
00:51:58.080
television, can't accomplish exactly what writing does, then they infer that television is
00:52:04.080
inferior to writing.
00:52:05.040
Well, my point is that, well, it's inferior to writing insofar as writing's accomplishments
00:52:12.160
are concerned, but writing is also inferior to television,
00:52:15.840
insofar as televisions are accomplishments.
00:52:18.160
In other words, each medium can do things that the other medium can't.
00:52:22.800
And what I'm interested in is finding out what it is about television in particular.
00:52:27.760
That makes it worthwhile.
00:52:30.240
Not for a moment denying that 99.8% of what we see on television is terrible,
00:52:37.680
which I think is also true of 99.8% of all the writing in the world, probably more.
00:52:41.760
Or 99.8% of novels that have been written, or of sonatas that have been written,
00:52:48.720
so on and so on and so forth.
00:52:50.000
We forget that, especially with established media and genres.
00:52:54.880
We think, well, the novel is a great job because we think of Ulysses and Prus and Thomas
00:52:59.040
Mann and Jane Austen not forgetting, I mean, forgetting that, apart from all the novels that have
00:53:06.640
been published and have been consigned to complete oblivion.
00:53:13.840
Millions that haven't even been published because they were too bad to publish.
00:53:18.320
Whereas with television, of course, we also--
00:53:21.600
So what does that television can do at its best?
00:53:24.000
Well, it changed one of the things about television, of course,
00:53:27.920
is that being a new medium, relatively speaking,
00:53:30.480
though it now is becoming old enough so that everybody's more willing to consider it as
00:53:35.600
interesting an art and it's no longer-- and you don't know a long and need to apologize for watching it.
00:53:40.560
The still people say, I don't watch television.
00:53:42.800
Well, there were people I'm sure in Plato's time who said I don't read.
00:53:46.720
I only listened.
00:53:50.160
Well, what do you say that I don't go to tragedies?
00:53:52.080
Well, most of them did, but the best among us, exactly, knew how bad they were.
00:53:59.040
Sure, of course.
00:53:59.760
And all that again goes back to Plato because his famous prescription of poetry
00:54:04.880
from the ideal state of the republic is the quintessential argument against popular culture,
00:54:11.200
which was tragedy at the time.
00:54:13.920
Just open up an entity and talk about that for a minute.
00:54:18.880
He has three reasons that he sort of is very suspicious of poetry, tragic and epic mostly,
00:54:26.000
but others as well.
00:54:27.040
It conflates the authentic and the fake.
00:54:29.840
It suited only for representing or best suited for representing violent and sexual subjects.
00:54:36.960
And it has the capacity of perverting even the best among us into acting in life
00:54:45.120
as we would have been ashamed to act had we not been exposed to it, which is, I think, the core,
00:54:50.080
the kernel, expressing one's emotions excessively, for example.
00:54:53.920
That's right.
00:54:54.480
And generally speaking, moving away from the path to not a genetic,
00:54:59.200
and that's another way in which beauty, of course, is considered to be dangerous, seductive.
00:55:05.760
Now, here are some things that some kind of television can do because, again,
00:55:12.960
you don't want to generalize in this case.
00:55:15.120
It allows us to see aspects of character that the novel can't quite do.
00:55:24.160
Television A up to now when the screens were slightly smaller was extremely intimate.
00:55:33.120
It's always close shooting, right?
00:55:37.120
It's always very narrow shots.
00:55:39.600
So you're always seeing faces very, very close, much closer than you see them either in cinema
00:55:46.800
or especially in the theater, where you're at a very, very great distance.
00:55:51.360
So you see people very intimately in ways that you can't see them in film or theater,
00:55:57.280
where it's much more important to project.
00:56:00.080
And one of the reasons that I've noticed that theater actors are very often not particularly good
00:56:05.520
in television is that theater actors are trained to shout, but seem as if they're speaking.
00:56:11.360
If you try to do that on television with a microphone in front of your mouth,
00:56:17.360
in a camera that's focusing on every little move in your very, every movement in your face,
00:56:23.040
you will seem ridiculous.
00:56:24.880
So you need to change.
00:56:26.240
So here it is acting is a different practice in theater, in film and in television.
00:56:33.760
So intimacy is something that television does.
00:56:35.920
Another thing that it does, and I think it's no accident that so many shows on television have to do
00:56:41.040
with the working place, is that it shows people in routine situations in sort of a background
00:56:48.720
which remains the same from week to week, but in very different specific quandaries,
00:56:54.400
such as every week.
00:56:55.600
The way that it portrays character is very different from the way that the novel portrays character,
00:57:01.920
the novel aims at showing you the essence of what a person is,
00:57:06.080
finding out what makes Anaka Renina work.
00:57:10.640
So to speak, what kind of person is it?
00:57:12.480
Is she?
00:57:13.280
And everything that Anaka Renina does springs from a certain complex of features that ultimately fit
00:57:20.640
together in a, I mean, it has to fit together, she's not a good character.
00:57:25.440
Now, what happens with television characters is that you see them in different situations every week,
00:57:30.880
and you end up seeing how many different aspects of fasts as a situation their character has,
00:57:37.840
without necessarily being able to make a simple overall judgment about them,
00:57:42.960
which is when you think about it very much the way we know most of the people that we're not
00:57:47.520
intimately acquainted with.
00:57:49.360
Right.
00:57:49.840
My colleagues, I mean, I know this colleague of mine is extremely bright, but it doesn't have
00:57:54.800
very good taste or this other has this very positive feature, but this other negative feature.
00:58:01.280
I don't try to say good or bad in general, what is in the novel? We do that.
00:58:05.440
And television gives us what I think is a highly realistic and very accurate picture of one aspect
00:58:10.880
of our relationship to the world and to other people.
00:58:12.800
We will have more from Alexander Nehemas in the second half of this conversation.
00:58:20.240
For now, I hope you'll agree with me that we've established the following.
00:58:24.800
First, a love of beauty is something more or less universal.
00:58:28.160
Second, it cuts across so-called high and low aesthetic genres.
00:58:32.800
Television shows can be just as beautiful and gripping and powerful and meaningful in our lives
00:58:37.680
as operas. Third, it doesn't yield knowledge necessarily anyway,
00:58:43.360
unless it's knowledge of the artwork itself, and it doesn't yield moral improvement.
00:58:47.760
But what it does yield, if I understand you correctly, is first of all,
00:58:51.440
some kind of distinctiveness in myself. And secondly,
00:58:56.480
a pertinent and a micro-community, a kind of utopian community where they're formed,
00:59:02.720
not on the basis of contingent features like one's origins, or one's class, or something like that,
00:59:09.600
but something much deeper about us. And finally, and this is something that we'll get to in the
00:59:13.760
second half that they have just an unpredictable way of changing our lives.
00:59:17.360
Very good. I agree with almost everything. Wonderful. So, Alexander, thank you very much.
00:59:24.240
Thank you.
00:59:26.000
[Music]
00:59:54.960
(soft music)