table of contents

04/25/2012

Debra Satz on John Rawls

Debra Satz, the Marta Sutton Weeks Professor of Ethics in Society, is the senior associate dean for the humanities and arts. Satz, a philosophy professor, directs the McCoy Family Center for Ethics in Society. She earned a bachelor’s degree from City College of New York and a doctorate in philosophy from Massachusetts Institute of Technology. […]

download transcript [vtt]
00:00:00.000
[ Music ]
00:00:07.000
This is KZSU Stanford.
00:00:10.500
Welcome to entitled opinions.
00:00:12.660
My name is Robert Harrison, and we're coming to you
00:00:16.000
from the Stanford campus.
00:00:18.000
[ Music ]
00:00:29.000
[ Music ]
00:00:52.000
Six score and seven years ago, Nietzsche's madman went into the marketplace
00:00:57.000
bright morning hours with a lantern in his hand.
00:01:01.000
He was looking for God.
00:01:02.000
He said to the people there,
00:01:04.000
many of whom didn't believe in God,
00:01:06.000
and started mocking him.
00:01:08.000
Where is he gone?
00:01:09.000
Did he lose his way like a child, they asked?
00:01:13.000
Where has God gone?
00:01:14.000
Cryed the madman?
00:01:15.000
I will tell you we have killed him.
00:01:18.000
You and I, we are all his murderers.
00:01:22.000
But how have we done this?
00:01:23.000
What did we do when we unchained?
00:01:26.000
This earth from its sun?
00:01:28.000
Where is it moving now?
00:01:30.000
Aren't we straying as through an infinite nothing?
00:01:34.000
Isn't the greatness of this deed too great for us?
00:01:38.000
The people fell silent and stared at him in astonishment.
00:01:42.000
He threw his lantern on the ground, it shattered and went out.
00:01:46.000
I come to early, said the madman,
00:01:48.000
deeds need time after they have been done.
00:01:51.000
This deed is still more distant from them than the most distant stars.
00:01:55.000
And yet we have done it ourselves.
00:01:59.000
Question.
00:02:00.000
Why did Nietzsche's madman go into the marketplace?
00:02:03.000
What do markets have to do with the death of God?
00:02:06.000
[Music]
00:02:10.000
[Music]
00:02:14.000
[Music]
00:02:18.000
[Music]
00:02:22.000
[Music]
00:02:26.000
[Music]
00:02:30.000
[Music]
00:02:34.000
[Music]
00:02:38.000
[Music]
00:02:42.000
[Music]
00:02:46.000
Looks so good, it looks so cool.
00:02:48.000
What does that mean?
00:02:49.000
God is dead and that we,
00:02:51.000
modern Western humanity killed him.
00:02:54.000
It means, first of all, that God no longer founds,
00:02:57.000
no longer informs and orders are world.
00:03:01.000
Second of all, it means that this so-called death is a historical event,
00:03:06.000
a world historical event to speak Hegelian.
00:03:10.000
If I remove God from the picture, I understand nothing of the art,
00:03:14.000
philosophy, cosmology, or politics of the Middle Ages.
00:03:18.000
Nothing of its rituals and practices.
00:03:21.000
By contrast, if I remove God from the modern world,
00:03:25.000
it's still the same world.
00:03:28.000
Not so when it comes to science and technology,
00:03:31.000
and even less so when it comes to money.
00:03:34.000
Nothing about the world we live in today makes any sense at all
00:03:38.000
if I subtract money from the equation.
00:03:41.000
So Nietzsche's madman was clear-voyant when he chose the marketplace
00:03:46.000
to announce the news that God is dead.
00:03:49.000
He foresaw that in the wake of God's demise,
00:03:52.000
the modern world as a whole was bound to become one vast,
00:03:57.000
all-consuming, all-encompassing marketplace,
00:04:01.000
where the universal currency of money would now take the place
00:04:05.000
that God had previously occupied.
00:04:09.000
The modern marketplace should have a sign over it that reads,
00:04:13.000
"Beyond good and evil."
00:04:16.000
Everything in this new temple is a good, as long as it has exchange value.
00:04:22.000
Even evil can be bought and sold,
00:04:25.000
hence even evil gets turned into a good by the marketplace.
00:04:30.000
I'm not sure that's what Nietzsche had in mind
00:04:33.000
when he talked about moving beyond good and evil.
00:04:35.000
In fact, I'm sure that's not what he had in mind,
00:04:38.000
but such is the A morality or trans morality or post morality
00:04:43.000
of the awesome market forces that are reconfiguring the contemporary world order as we speak.
00:04:51.000
"La jafilighe," Napoleon declared, "money makes wars."
00:04:57.000
We now know that it makes a whole lot more than wars.
00:05:00.000
It makes and unmakes and remakes just about everything.
00:05:04.000
The person who joins me in the studio today is recently written a book entitled,
00:05:09.000
"Why Some Things Should Not Be For Sale," subtitle,
00:05:14.000
"The Moral Limits of Markets," the moral limits of markets.
00:05:20.000
Later on our show, I ask her whether the word "should" as in why some things should not be for sale,
00:05:28.000
still has any currency in our market-driven world,
00:05:32.000
and whether the phrase "The Moral Limits of Markets" has any swaetion among its major protagonist
00:05:38.000
today.
00:05:39.000
But first, let me introduce her to you.
00:05:41.000
Deborah Sats is the "Marda" Sutton Weeks Professor of Ethics in Society,
00:05:46.000
and Professor of Philosophy here at Stanford.
00:05:49.000
In addition to her book on the moral limits of markets,
00:05:52.000
she has worked on the place of equality and political philosophy,
00:05:56.000
on theories of rational choice, on democracy, feminist philosophy,
00:06:01.000
and issues of international justice,
00:06:04.000
will be posting other details about her impressive academic profile
00:06:09.000
on the entitled "Pinience Website," so Deborah, welcome to our program.
00:06:14.000
It's good to be here.
00:06:16.000
Before we discuss your new book about markets,
00:06:19.000
I'd like to ask you if you would kindly share a few thoughts with us about John Rawls,
00:06:24.000
the author of that very influential book of political philosophy,
00:06:28.000
called "Theory of Justice," that was published in 1971,
00:06:32.000
a number of people who listened to entitled "Pinience" have lobbied me over the years
00:06:37.000
for a show about John Rawls,
00:06:39.000
and I can't think of anyone better suited to discuss John Rawls than you,
00:06:44.000
because I know that Rawls has been very important for your work on equality,
00:06:48.000
and you don't shy away from identifying yourself as a Rawlsian,
00:06:52.000
at least when I asked you, you did not shy away from saying, "Yes, I am a Rawlsian."
00:06:57.000
In preparing for this show, I read somewhere a quote by someone named Jonathan Wolf to the effect,
00:07:03.000
now quoting,
00:07:04.000
"Well, there might be a dispute about the second most important political philosopher of the 20th century,
00:07:10.000
there could be no dispute about the most important."
00:07:14.000
John Rawls.
00:07:16.000
Well, I think there can be some dispute about that.
00:07:20.000
At least personally, I don't agree with that.
00:07:22.000
I think that Hannah Arendt for me would be the most important political philosopher
00:07:26.000
of the 20th century, but leaving that aside, do you agree with Wolf about Rawlsian importance in political philosophy?
00:07:33.000
I think it's hard to underestimate Rawls' influence on political philosophy and beyond,
00:07:40.000
I think, and in a couple of substantial ways.
00:07:44.000
One is the subject wasn't seen a central to philosophy and to political philosophy in the 20th century
00:07:53.000
before Rawls wrote.
00:07:55.000
The 20th century philosophy tended to be dominated by issues in logic and epistemology and metaphysics and philosophy of science.
00:08:05.000
Rawls put political philosophy and ethics back on the map as serious subjects that analytic philosophers could contribute to.
00:08:17.000
That's one thing, just in terms of making the subject speak.
00:08:23.000
But there were two other things about Rawls' theory that I think are really important.
00:08:28.000
The dominant view, both in philosophy and then in common sense thinking about justice, was a form of utilitarianism.
00:08:40.000
The idea that the right thing to do was what maximized the greatest happiness of the greatest numbers, the slogan for utilitarianism,
00:08:50.000
and that theory had and still has a hold on many people.
00:08:58.000
It points to the importance of consequences, it points to the importance of well-being in thinking about justice.
00:09:06.000
But it has some untoward consequences, as was often shown by the idea that you could sacrifice an innocent person and produce a bit more happiness.
00:09:17.000
Rawls saw it as his charge to work at an alternative theory of justice to the dominant utilitarian theory.
00:09:26.000
So that's a second reason he's so influential, is that he developed, revived a tradition of thought that was an alternative to utilitarianism and did it with 20th century analytic tools.
00:09:43.000
And I think third is he developed a theory that's very systematic and it's hard to build a systematic theory and it's a big book and it has a lot of parts to it.
00:09:56.000
And it's not just a little piece of an issue, it really tries to tackle the kind of biggest question we face as a society, which is, you know, in thinking about our institutions and how we arrange them, what's fair,
00:10:11.000
what do we owe each other? And Rawls tries to give us a way of thinking about that.
00:10:17.000
Well, there are that word fairs come up, you know, as if justice equals fairness and he's very well known for defining justice as a kind of fairness and we can talk about what exactly that means.
00:10:30.000
Because you and I have talked about this before that the word fair cannot be really translated into romance languages, for example, and I looked it up, you know, at a melodically it really comes from beautiful and light and so there's nothing in the history of the use of that word which would seem to make it the natural correlate of justice.
00:10:52.000
And even the word justice, I was, you know, I'd like to get a historical perspective on these things and that word's not that ancient.
00:11:01.000
So the first question I'd like to ask you about utilitarianism and that was the reigning concept of justice.
00:11:08.000
Obviously justice works within a legal framework independently of philosophers coming up with theories of it.
00:11:16.000
So our constitution is supposed to be that which safeguards, you know, the functioning of the of the, at least the system of justice that we associate with positive law.
00:11:27.000
What importance has utilitarianism had as in when it comes to the question of justice, my first question, then I'll ask you what importance Rawls has had when it comes to the influence that that it may have had or not had in the actual practice of the administration of justice.
00:11:45.000
Well, I think so historically utilitarianism was very concerned about law, Jeremy Bentham and John Mill who were the, you know, early proponents of the theory.
00:11:59.000
We're very concerned to reform law along utilitarian lines because they thought the justification for coercion has to be the contribution that that coercion makes to improving the well-being of people.
00:12:16.000
And so they, for example, argued against laws that, for example, victimless crimes, which they thought had no external bad effects and simply curtailed an individual's freedom for no positive end.
00:12:32.000
So they were very clear on that and they thought laws needed to be reformed and that in thinking about punishment, taxation, the distribution of wealth, the vote, we ought to reform laws.
00:12:45.000
So that they benefit the most amount of people.
00:12:48.000
And I think that thinking has been very influential and is extremely powerful.
00:12:54.000
We often point in the justification of regulations by the government to the fact that these regulations serve the interests of everybody.
00:13:02.000
They serve to make people better off than they would have been in the absence of those regulations.
00:13:08.000
And that thinking, which not only permeates the justification of regulatory law, is also very influential in economics where we, you know, constantly are looking to improvements that can be made in terms of efficiency and justifying them because they make people better off than they would have been in the absence of those.
00:13:31.000
Let's take, in the case of markets, different kinds of exchanges.
00:13:35.000
I think that's a very live and many of our norms are tracking individual well-being.
00:13:45.000
The Rawlsian response is to take another strain of our law and go back to the idea of a different way of justifying policies beyond their maximizing effect on well-being.
00:14:02.000
And to ask, you know, are these laws and rules that the people who are live under them would agree to have?
00:14:11.000
So to think about the justification to people and one way Rawls thinks about this is, under a set of arrangements, if you could justify to the person who's made worse off under these arrangements, still that they're better off with these arrangements than alternatives, then you've succeeded in justifying.
00:14:31.000
And the test of whether or not people would accept a set of arrangements, whether they could be justified to everyone is different than the justification that proceeds in terms of maximizing the greatest happiness of the greatest number, because the maximization might take place even though some people wouldn't consent to it.
00:14:52.000
Okay, well, I have a few questions. I love having a philosopher in the studio's because then you can get into, you know, the little knitting griddle that he's arguing.
00:15:02.000
If I were to leaving aside Rawlsian here for a moment, talking about the utilitarian concept of justice, which has had all this importance, what if I were to say that, no, the way I see it, at least from the point of view of the American Constitution, is that the primary purpose of justice is not to maximize the greatest good for the government.
00:15:21.000
The greatest good for the greatest number, but on the contrary, it's to assure protection for minorities. It's to assure that the individual rights are not trampled on by the demands of the majority, and that therefore our whole system is intensely aware of how it's, in some cases, even the minority of one must win out over the majority of the all.
00:15:50.000
So I think the American Constitution clearly reflects a different tradition from utilitarianism, even though there are utilitarian-like elements in our laws. And one of the things we're all said was his hope in his theory of justice, was to take an earlier tradition of the social contract, the tradition which tries to justify through something like hypothetical consent, and move it to a whole system.
00:16:19.000
And move it to a higher level of abstraction. And that's the tradition of people like John Locke and Rousseau and Hobbes. And Locke, of course, was very, very influential in the American Constitution and the idea of the protection of individual basic liberties, even when protecting those liberties, you know, wouldn't make a majority very happy, because there are liberties of a minority that's disliked is a fundamental part of our Constitution.
00:16:48.000
So, Roles wasn't, you know, he's very radical in some ways, but he's not radical in many ways. He starts from very widely shared what he calls fixed points of our thinking and culture, you know, at the 20th century. And some of these are found in our Constitution, the idea of individuals as free and equal.
00:17:15.000
And he takes that as a fixed point so that any theory of justice that can't accommodate that point is to be rejected.
00:17:24.000
And then he tries from that very minimal, intuitive idea to build up to some pretty radical conclusions about the kind of economy we should have and about the obligations we have to other people.
00:17:39.000
Well, there again, that word should have, it comes in, so we'll talk about the should. You mentioned liberty and equality or freedom and equality and you're alluding to his famous two principles. Can you tell us something about what the two principles are in the theory of justice?
00:17:54.000
Sure. Although I have to say, to me, is always seem that there are three principles, not two principles, although he calls it as two principles. And I'll explain why.
00:18:04.000
So, Raul says, the theory of justice he's defending can be understood as composed of these two parts.
00:18:15.000
A first principle, which is the equal basic liberty principle, which says, every citizen is entitled to a package of basic freedoms where those freedoms are the same as those that other citizens have, or every member of the society.
00:18:32.000
And those are equal in a formal way, you might think they're equally guaranteed by law. Now, Raul says in that first principle, there's one exception to the formal guarantee of these.
00:18:46.000
And that is with respect to political liberty, which he thinks we have to treat in a different way. He says political liberties should be distributed to people, not so that they just have them as equal under the law.
00:18:59.000
But every person who's similarly talented and able should have the same opportunity to influence the political process and the same opportunity to run for office.
00:19:09.000
And that's already a very egalitarian constraint on basic liberty and one, I think our society has moved quite far away from in the current dominance of money and politics.
00:19:22.000
So could we call that freedom of opportunity?
00:19:26.000
So the equal basic liberty principle is really about guarantees of certain kinds of rights that people hold.
00:19:39.000
The second principle is more of an opportunity principle.
00:19:43.000
So, Raul's is second principle says, and the second principle has two parts, which is why I said it's really a three principle theory.
00:19:53.000
The second principle says, "Goods in the society basic goods that people need in order to make those freedoms real so that they're not just formal, so that basic liberties should have said include things like freedom of conscience, freedom of religion, freedom of expression.
00:20:12.000
To make those things real people need certain kinds of goods, they need opportunities, they need resources, they need a certain level of income and wealth."
00:20:23.000
And so Raul says, "These goods that they need, which he calls primary goods, should be distributed according to two principles.
00:20:33.000
The first is a fair quality of opportunity principle, and that says people in the society should have the same life chances, if they're similarly talented and able, their income class of birth shouldn't affect their life chances.
00:20:50.000
It shouldn't affect their opportunity to occupy different positions of power and prestige in the society.
00:20:56.000
We're not a caste society, class shouldn't be destiny."
00:21:00.000
And the second part of that principle says these primary goods should be distributed so that inequalities in them are justified when they improve the position of the least well-off person, meaning there's an efficiency justification for allowing the inequalities.
00:21:18.000
We don't get to earn more than somebody else, just on some basis of pre-political desert, we think about what people deserve and what they're owed in the cooperative scheme of a society by thinking about how those rewards affect what other people have.
00:21:39.000
I should say that Raul's theory is limited in scope. I mean, the two principles of justice don't apply to everything. They don't apply to how my husband and I decide to divvy up the evening's tasks of dishwashing.
00:21:58.000
They are meant to apply to what Raul's calls the basic structure of society and that's the system of law, the basic institutions, the market, the economy, government, the public sphere.
00:22:11.000
They do apply to the family in some ways, although they don't apply to every action in the family and they don't apply to individuals.
00:22:20.000
When I make decisions, as long as I'm operating within the bounds of a just society, I don't have to make my decisions according to the difference principle.
00:22:31.000
I don't have to decide where to go to dinner on the basis of that it maximizes the position of the least well-off person, these apply to the basic set of institutions that compose the society.
00:22:44.000
Raul's theory of justice presuppose a well-developed or advanced state that would be the central agency of distribution.
00:22:56.000
Raul's theory is what's sometimes referred to as ideal theory, so there's a whole set of background assumptions. One is that the society is relatively well-ordered, meaning people have a sense of justice and are willing to comply with the principles of justice, the institutions function fairly well.
00:23:18.000
The society is not so poor or so under-resourced that it can't meet, so if you think that allowing basic liberties can be costly, some societies might not be able to give a full package of the basic liberties in non-ideal circumstances because they're too poor and because they've got to do certain things to feed themselves.
00:23:44.000
So Raul's thought the two principles only apply against a certain background that's idealized and then we can approximate or not approximate.
00:23:55.000
In non-ideal conditions he thought the two principles might still apply but they might not be ordered.
00:24:02.000
I should say something about that because that's relevant to the issue about utilitarianism.
00:24:08.000
In most thought his two principles have what he called the lexical ordering, meaning you have to satisfy the first principle before you can move down to the second part of the second principle and then to the second part of the second principle.
00:24:24.000
So I can't trade off basic liberties against income and wealth. The assumption in the ideal theory is my interest in my basic liberties, my freedom of expression, religion, association are so fundamental that these have to have a protection against income and wealth and improving the position of the lease well off person.
00:24:48.000
In non-ideal circumstances he said we could make these trade offs.
00:24:52.000
Right. So it does presuppose these ideal cases and I think it presupposes a long history.
00:25:00.000
One of my most important influences is an 18th century thinker Italian Thigr name, John Batista Vico, who wrote the new science where he tries to reconstruct how we got from an age of severe kind of primitive
00:25:16.000
gigantism to finally after many centuries if not millennia to a kind of aristocracy society and then after many revolutions and plebeian travails and so forth we finally get the rudiments of a republican system of government and then finally we get democracies, a long, long history that seems to be presupposed by a Rawlsian theory of justice that our forebears have gone through an extraordinary process of evolution where now we can think.
00:25:45.000
I think rationally and reasonably and that we can engage in what he calls this experiment of the veil of ignorance but it seems to presuppose that all citizens within this ideal society are rational and reasonable agents now.
00:26:03.000
I think there are a lot of background pieces of machinery in the Rawlsian story and as I said one of the most important ones is he begins with what he takes to be fixed points.
00:26:19.000
Fix points are these beliefs and commitments we have that we don't expect to change their fundamental they're like the laws of logic and mathematics and those are the people are free and equal.
00:26:36.000
Well of course the idea that people are free and equal is a historical achievement for that idea to have taken hold and the theory doesn't get off the ground in the context of people who would reject that idea because it's one of the building blocks of the theory when we're constructing a theory of justice where all things were constructing it out of some of our intuitions and then we're subjecting those intuitions to critical reflection.
00:27:05.000
But we've got to take those intuitions into the picture there's no view here from nowhere there's no God's eye view it's us thinking for ourselves in the context of the world we live in and our best judgments what's the best set of institutions for us what's fair how should we live.
00:27:23.000
And I guess the question there is what degree of universality he pretends to because the notion of fairness is one that it's almost like a transcendental and it's something that should have a universal consent so I have two questions for you one is is the theory of justice as fairness compatible with a view of life.
00:27:45.000
That was expressed by John F. Kennedy who said famously life is not fair.
00:27:52.000
Can life in its essence not be fair and we still need a theory of justice because we aspire to it as an ideal because it actually contradicts the fundamental unfairness of life.
00:28:05.000
So the really interesting question I don't think the purpose of the of Rawls's theory is to make life fair it's a political theory aimed at the institutions we make.
00:28:21.000
So our laws our economy the way we distribute wealth our tax system our education system it governs those but life is a lot bigger than those now there's some people who think the point of a theory of justice ought to be right from you know from the point of view of the universe to create fairness.
00:28:45.000
That's not that's not the Rawlsian project I don't think that's a plausible project because I think that life is inevitably full of things that happen to us that we can't control.
00:29:01.000
And that there is no and one of the main ones is death and the fact that for all of us we die and people we love die and no theory of justice can redress you know the experience of losing people you love.
00:29:17.000
That's true losing people you love it but I guess I come from a continental philosophical position where death is not unfair death is the very conditioned matrix of life in any cases not that is so far.
00:29:30.000
That is not that is a fulfillment not that just the termination of life that last question.
00:29:35.000
Point taken.
00:29:36.000
Last question for you Deborah before we talk about your book about the markets I came across again preparing for the show I want to read you that following quote and ask ask you to respond to it John Rawls failure to consider non ideal cases.
00:29:50.000
And that would go with this frequent use of the word should.
00:29:55.000
Quote is not a tiny mole that serves as a beauty spot to set off the radiance of the rest of the face but the epidermal sign of a lethal tumor.
00:30:07.000
And then that's over the top it's really actually bad.
00:30:11.000
It's just bad metaphorics or imagery but how do you how do you respond to that that is failure to consider non ideal cases is a lethal flaw in the system or the theory.
00:30:22.000
So I think the question is whether or not the kind of theory Rawls builds is guiding for us in the non ideal world that we live in.
00:30:34.000
And one of the things Rawls said he was trying to do with his theory of justice was in this is a quote to provide guidance where guidance is needed.
00:30:44.000
So he thought doing this kind of theory construction can help us when we find our intuitions and our policies and our laws are in conflict.
00:30:54.000
And I think the proof of the pudding is to what extent it's guiding and I actually think in some important respects it has been guiding there are a lot of policy debates where Rawls has had a huge influence one of them is in the whole issue of how should health care be distributed and how should we think about our obligations to people with respect to the provision of medical care.
00:31:21.000
Another is in education and so people who are involved in thinking through our non ideal world will draw on Rawls's theory for guidance.
00:31:32.000
I'm sympathetic I mean my own work is at a lower level of abstraction than Rawls is is.
00:31:40.000
And so I'm sympathetic that we sometimes have to push ourselves back down to the messy world.
00:31:47.000
But I think abstraction and critical reflection are tools we need and use in their part of the messy world.
00:31:55.000
And so I think with all due respect to Raymond Goyce it is over the top.
00:32:01.000
Good enough. Good enough. That's great.
00:32:04.000
So moving now on to your book about why something should not be for sale.
00:32:08.000
This is a book about the the hegemony if it's not too strong a term of the of the marketplace today and how there are a number of people who believe that the market is.
00:32:16.000
If you let the market regulate our interactions everything will be for the better maybe the greater, you know the greatest number.
00:32:25.000
And you you take issue with some of the presuppositions that underlie some of the discourses about the marketplace today, you know.
00:32:35.000
And you've written this very interesting book about why something should not be for sale in which you do try to get down now in to the more concrete realms.
00:32:45.000
And fine nevertheless abstract well let's say philosophical are reasoned arguments.
00:32:52.000
Principal arguments.
00:32:54.000
Moral arguments about why certain things should not be for sale.
00:32:58.000
So can I ask you first question how Rawlsian do you consider this book that came out in 2010?
00:33:05.000
So there are a couple of Rawlsian tropes in this book.
00:33:10.000
One is that I'm thinking about institutions and a basic structure and social arrangements and I'm trying to apply principles to that rather than to individual actions and that's a Rawlsian you know that the concerns of justice are really about institutions primarily.
00:33:31.000
A second Rawlsian piece of this is I'm trying as much as possible to shy away from particular views about the good life or human flourishing.
00:33:47.000
So one of the things the Rawlsian project we didn't talk about the veil of ignorance but one of the things Rawls was trying to do in designing his two principles was to think about principles that could be accepted by people.
00:34:00.000
Who disagree about value in life like what makes a life good.
00:34:06.000
One of the other fixed points of Rawls's theory was what he called the fact of reasonable pluralism.
00:34:15.000
The fact that in the absence of state coercion reasonable people will disagree about what gives meaning to life.
00:34:21.000
So when I approach the issue of what are the limits of markets, I didn't take a view which has sometimes been taken by people in this literature interested in this topic who think, well the reason not to distribute certain kinds of goods according to markets is because there's a certain appropriate way of valuing those goods and when we sell those goods we debase their value.
00:34:50.000
Well I think there's something to be said on behalf of that argument, I think the worry is that people disagree about the meaning of certain goods.
00:35:02.000
And one of the nice things about a market is you and I could disagree about religion and we could buy and sell a Bible.
00:35:10.000
And the fact that I sell a Bible doesn't necessarily express my attitude towards the Bible any more than you're buying of it.
00:35:21.000
But there is a view what Michael Sandell's just written a book on this that comes out of his tenor lectures and Michael Walzer and other people have argued that there's an appropriate way to value goods and markets debase the currency of those goods.
00:35:38.000
When I say there's something to the argument you can think about a good like friendship and you can think, well look if you try to buy a friend, whatever you buy, it's not a friend you've debased the good and if there's an appropriate way of having a friend you've now destroyed that.
00:35:56.000
I think that in a very limited set of goods are like that but in many goods we can have plural understandings and then in a liberal society we don't want to impose one way of valuing a good on people.
00:36:09.000
And so arguments that press the limits of markets solely on the basis of you should view this good in this way I think are a liberal.
00:36:20.000
Whereas you are dealing with some things that you don't think should enter into the place of exchange and you are not, you claim I correct understand you correctly that you're not putting forward moral arguments as such but you're in more social political arguments for why the trafficking in certain kinds of goods works against principles.
00:36:49.000
of either equality or of human dignity.
00:36:55.000
So I'm putting forward moral arguments but they're not based on specific views about what makes a life good.
00:37:04.000
So but I am trying to single out features of certain kinds of markets that I think are worrying actually from the point of view of a democratic society.
00:37:18.000
That's the political argument.
00:37:21.000
It's an ethical argument embedded in a political argument about democracy.
00:37:26.000
So if we're going to have a democratic society of society of people who are free and equal there are certain kinds of goods whose sale is problematic.
00:37:37.000
But for example and we can get into the goods that you find not just as you say, prostitution for example.
00:37:45.000
So in your chapter on prostitution why you don't think that the selling of sexual services should be marketed.
00:37:57.000
That you're saying that you're not taking again the moral stand from the point of view of sex is bad outside of marriage or something of that sort but rather that there is a certain way where sexual services when they enter the marketplace degrade the women in general in this society.
00:38:14.000
There are social and political consequences to certain knock-off markets if I understand you correctly.
00:38:23.000
That's right.
00:38:24.000
So I'm interested in some of the effects that worry me are what are third party effects.
00:38:30.000
So there are not effects on the parties to an exchange but there are effects that spill over into other kinds of exchanges that affect the ability of people in a society to stand as equals.
00:38:43.000
So, you know, some people are too poor, right?
00:38:47.000
This is kind of a so idea that no man should be rich enough or poor enough that one man is forced right to work for another one.
00:38:58.000
There should be no such extremes of desperation.
00:39:02.000
When you have people who are desperate they can't stand together as equals some bow and scrape before the higher born.
00:39:09.000
So some kinds of markets child labor is another, I think not so controversial example where many most forms of child labor prevent children from developing the capacities that they need to see themselves as, you know, people can make claims, stand as equal, get an education, understand alternatives.
00:39:29.000
There are also third party effects of child labor on other people.
00:39:34.000
And so one of the things I look at in the book are markets who have, who's, markets with effects that are different than apples.
00:39:45.000
You know, if you think of apples as a kind of canonical market, we buy and sell apples.
00:39:50.000
We don't worry that much unless the apples become poisoned or there's some issues about the way the farm laborers are treated.
00:39:57.000
We don't worry about the spillover effects of apples.
00:40:00.000
But there are other markets, particularly markets dealing that deal with human beings, where we do worry about the effects of certain kinds of markets on people's ability to understand themselves as free and equal citizens.
00:40:14.000
And actually I go back and the book and look a little bit at the history of political economy and Adam Smith, who's often seen as the great celebrator of the free market,
00:40:26.000
was very concerned about some of the effects of labor markets in degrading, he said,
00:40:34.000
and unless we have intervention in the form of public education, we should worry about the effects of certain kinds of markets in making people into beings that are unfit to be citizens.
00:40:46.000
Well, okay, let's speak about a few examples because you do an excellent job in your proposing the counter arguments to the arguments that you end up making.
00:40:56.000
And if you take, for example, child labor laws, you say that there are some arguments that do actually make sense that if you forbid markets in child labor, you might be forcing those children into child prostitution, which would have a much more noxious effect on the end of the year.
00:41:15.000
And so on.
00:41:16.000
So, you have a question on the individual's question as well as on the society and so forth, but you think that you have criteria by which you can actually adjudicate why it's still the right thing to do to forbid markets in child labor, even though sometimes the consequences could be worse.
00:41:38.000
So.
00:41:39.000
What are these criteria? How do you arrive at them?
00:41:43.000
So, one of the things, again, the kind of Rawlsian trope, I start and look at a bunch of reactions people have to different kinds of markets.
00:41:52.000
And maybe these reactions have, you know, are just repugnance that can't be analyzed.
00:41:58.000
But I want to take these at their face and then think about whether or not there's something behind our reactions.
00:42:04.000
So, people have very different reactions to child labor, kidney markets, actually education, health care than they do to Apple markets.
00:42:13.000
And so, one of the things I'm looking at is why is there anything that's going on?
00:42:18.000
And what I find is that there are a bunch of different kinds of considerations that we can lump all the markets that people find problematic together.
00:42:30.000
And in all of these cases, we'll find one of these, I have four considerations.
00:42:36.000
And not every market has all of these considerations, but every market we find problematic has at least one.
00:42:43.000
And the four parameters.
00:42:44.000
These are four parameters.
00:42:46.000
And they're what I consider the defining features of what I call an "noxious market," a market that people react to differently than an Apple market.
00:42:55.000
And those are extreme harm, very weak agency, inequality, and actually degrading of democracy.
00:43:07.000
>> A vulnerability.
00:43:08.000
>> And vulnerability is in the inequality.
00:43:12.000
So, take an example, child labor.
00:43:15.000
So, what are some features of a child labor market?
00:43:18.000
Well, children aren't real agents on the market.
00:43:21.000
I mean, they don't contract their labor, their parents do.
00:43:24.000
So, that's one form of weak agency.
00:43:26.000
They're not really parties.
00:43:28.000
But they're also weak agency because the parents who contract children's labor in very poor countries often don't know what the long-term consequences are of taking their kids out of school.
00:43:39.000
They don't have full information.
00:43:41.000
That's another form of weak agency.
00:43:43.000
There's harm to the individual children.
00:43:46.000
They don't develop the capacities to be able to take care of themselves, to be independent.
00:43:53.000
To stand up for their needs.
00:43:55.000
And their harms to society to democracy because children who are raised in child labor grow up to be adults who don't demand their rights.
00:44:04.000
So, I analyze the four parameters.
00:44:07.000
I analyze these problematic markets in terms of these different parameters.
00:44:11.000
I say when markets score high, there's a tipping point that makes them what are called "noxious."
00:44:17.000
And then the question is what to do.
00:44:19.000
>> Can I interrupt?
00:44:21.000
>> Can I interrupt?
00:44:22.000
I'm sorry, I'm sorry, but before we get to the question, what can we do?
00:44:26.000
Okay, this kind of revulsion or this intuitive, this is not good.
00:44:31.000
Again, like the Rawlsian question, how much of it presupposes a democratic society where we believe that children should be going to school, a podilisor, that child labor laws have existed since the early 20th century.
00:44:46.000
For the vast majority of our own ancestors in the Western world, children were put to work in the fields in the peasantry from a very early age.
00:44:57.000
And child labor has always been a kind of reality of agrarian agricultural society.
00:45:04.000
So, how culture-specific are these evaluations that you're making?
00:45:10.000
>> Well, so I think you can have a view of harm, and we can defend a view of harm that's not culturally specific.
00:45:20.000
When people are burned, they're harmed.
00:45:23.000
When people are absolutely not educated, they're harmed.
00:45:27.000
Now, of course, we haven't always been able to educate people, and there's an open question as to what extent in the world today, we can achieve full of education for all children.
00:45:39.000
There's also questions about, you know, can children work and go to school?
00:45:44.000
And there are also questions, I think, that are cultural about what kinds of labor are permissible or not permissible?
00:45:54.000
But a lot of the work that children do around the world, I don't think there's a culturally, you know, we should go the cultural relativists root here, because a lot of these kids are working in conditions, which,
00:46:08.000
undermine, dramatically, their health, their mental well-being, and so on.
00:46:15.000
>> Well, I'm always looking for ways to avoid cultural relativism, because I would like to find some other ground on which to make absolute statements and categorical statements.
00:46:28.000
And, you know, Kant's doctrine that a human being is not a means to an end, but is an end in himself or herself is something that I fundamentally believe,
00:46:37.000
when I'm committed to. On the other hand, I was reading last week or two weeks ago that there's Korean men now can go into Vietnam, and they can be in their 50s, but they can marry young, you know, 20-year-old Vietnamese if they send $100 a month back to the families, the girls that hand them over.
00:47:00.000
That's not fair. It's not exactly parallel to child labor, but it's a form of unfairness that one finds that it should be addressed to. Is that a marketplace that can be regulated? How much can we extend our fairness across the world?
00:47:18.000
>> So, I mean, those are lots of really good questions. Just to stay focused for one minute children are different than even 20-year-olds.
00:47:29.000
I mean, when we're talking about children, we're really talking about there's no volunteeriness here.
00:47:34.000
We're also talking about often circumstances in which the parents might want if they had any option not to put their kids to work.
00:47:43.000
I mean, one of the main drivers, of course, of child labor is poverty, and that gets to, I think, the issue of what to do, and my approach to the more limits of markets is even when you see that a market is not just, it doesn't mean that the right policy response is to ban the market.
00:48:02.000
Because if you ban simply go in and ban child labor, you might wind up with worse harm for children because they're driven underground to a black market where it's better for kids to work in regulated factories than to be child prostitutes or child soldiers.
00:48:19.000
So, what I think my approach does is help you think about the parameters and you think here are the things that are worrying.
00:48:31.000
Okay, how can I fix those things?
00:48:35.000
And if one of the things that's worrying is lack of education or harm, how can I then, if I close off this option of child labor, make sure the kids are in school?
00:48:46.000
Or, if I close off this alternative of somebody selling a body part, but I give them nothing else and the result is they starve, am I really addressing the problem of harm?
00:48:58.000
And so, sometimes the problem is, in some contexts, people don't understand what they're doing.
00:49:05.000
So, I had a student who wrote an undergraduate thesis on people selling their kidneys in India and went down and interviewed about 80 people who had sold their kidneys.
00:49:18.000
And one of the things he found out is that lots of people didn't know how many kidneys they had.
00:49:23.000
Well, one thing you might do, if you thought, if you thought that was the problem, the problem is people, then you'd think, okay, at least we have to have informed consent.
00:49:32.000
So, let's, we won't ban the market, but we'll actually make sure people understand what we're doing.
00:49:38.000
Well, if you think, no, the problem is in just weak agency, it's that there's some harm or there's some inequality aspect to this, then we need to address that.
00:49:47.000
And so, this partly gives you a way of thinking about when do you want to close off a market?
00:49:54.000
And if you close it off, in virtual wire, you're closing it off, and what do you need to do to make sure the thing you're concerned about doesn't come back.
00:50:01.000
Well, one question I would have then is, are there objective criteria for determining what is it, anxious market and what isn't?
00:50:11.000
So, I don't know if you know there's someone reviewed your book.
00:50:16.000
I came across it and you just talk about contract pregnancy as one of the things that you would not allow a market for.
00:50:25.000
And the reviewer who is very praising and sympathetic to your book, but nevertheless, she, in your book you say that the reasons that you would, you find it in the office is one.
00:50:38.000
This quote, "You contract pregnancy gives others increased access to and control over women's bodies and sexuality."
00:50:44.000
Not good.
00:50:45.000
Two contract pregnancy contributes to gender inequality by reinforcing negative stereotypes about women as baby machines.
00:50:53.000
And three contract pregnancy raises the danger that in contested cases of parental rights motherhood will be defined in terms of genetic material in the same way as fatherhood failing to recognize the unequal contributions of men and women to the birthing process where women's gestational labor is not equivalent to a man's genetic contribution."
00:51:15.000
Thank you.
00:51:17.000
Yeah. And the reviewer then says, "In response to these concerns, I would suggest one.
00:51:23.000
Contract pregnancy gives women a specialized medium for reclaiming control over their own bodies and its reproductive abilities despite social gender equality.
00:51:32.000
Two reproductive labor in certain forms reinforces negative stereotypes of men as sperm donors rather than active parental figures.
00:51:42.000
Every all cases of contested parenthood for both fathers and mothers should consider more than just the genetic relationship to the child."
00:51:51.000
So here you have your sense that it's bad for gender equality in the society, and here's another one of saying, "Well, no, maybe it's actually very good and it's correcting the stereotypes, not reinforcing it."
00:52:04.000
So are there objective criteria of evaluation when it comes to disagreements of this sort?
00:52:09.000
So my argument about contract pregnancy and prostitution is much more in the form of if these are the effects than we have reason to be concerned about these markets.
00:52:24.000
If they're not the effects, then we don't have reason to be concerned about those markets.
00:52:29.000
And I think we have social scientific ways imperfect, but of trying to measure what are the effects of allowing these kinds of markets.
00:52:40.000
I don't actually in the contract pregnancy case say that we shouldn't allow it. I say we shouldn't enforce it.
00:52:48.000
And enforcement has to do with if a woman enters into one of these agreements and changes her mind, should we enforce the delivery of a baby to the contracting parties?
00:53:04.000
And there I think that the weak agency argument has some hold, which is that before somebody is surrendered a child, and before they've been pregnant and had a child and had to surrender it,
00:53:16.000
they can't really know what it is that they're agreeing to.
00:53:19.000
So, and many people, I mean, not that many people change their mind in these contexts, but those who do actually, that's what they say, is that I had no idea I would bond with this child that I was carrying.
00:53:32.000
So again, you might think, well, the right response then is to really increase agency and make sure people know, or you might think we just should regulate it because the potential harm is so great.
00:53:43.000
That's great. The books have been out for a year at least now, and it's gotten a lot of attention I know, and you've been on the circuit for it, and is it having an impact there where it counts the most, namely in policy legislation and so forth?
00:54:01.000
I don't think so. You know, it's a book.
00:54:03.000
Is this a book more? You think it's more directed to philosophers or political theorists or words? It's a bit of a hybrid.
00:54:10.000
It's, you know, certainly gotten some reviews in economic journals, which has been great, and I've been very happy about that.
00:54:18.000
It's not, I think, I haven't seen anybody cite it in the legislature, but...
00:54:27.000
So the Supreme Court's not going to call you in as an expert counsel.
00:54:29.000
I don't think I'm going to be an expert witness, but, you know, I'm hoping that it complicates the way people view markets.
00:54:37.000
There's been a tendency to be very abstract in the way we think about markets and to think they're all the same, and to just think of them as represented by equations on a blackboard, and I want to recover an older tradition of really thinking through the heterogeneity of different kinds of markets and the heterogeneous effects they have.
00:54:57.000
Well, that's great. The book is Why Some Things Should Not Be For Sale by Deborah Sats, Oxford University Press. You can go and get that.
00:55:05.000
We've been speaking with Professor Deborah Sats here on entitled "Pinions." I'm Robert Harrison. You can access all our previous shows, either from our website or on our iTunes podcast.
00:55:15.000
Thank you very much for coming on. Deborah, it's been a pleasure to have you, and to talk about both John Rawls and the moral limits of markets.
00:55:23.000
It's been great. Thanks. Bye-bye.
00:55:25.000
[Music]
00:55:43.000
[Music]
00:56:07.000
[Music]
00:56:17.000
[Music]
00:56:25.000
[Music]
00:56:33.000
[Music]
00:56:43.000
[Music]
00:56:53.000
[Music]
00:57:01.000
[Music]
00:57:11.000
[Music]
00:57:15.000
[Music]
00:57:21.000
[Music]
00:57:31.000
[Music]
00:57:41.000
[Music]
00:57:51.000
[Music]
00:58:01.000
[Music]
00:58:11.000
[Music]
00:58:21.000
[Music]
00:58:25.000
[Music]
00:58:31.000
[Music]
00:58:41.000
[Music]
00:58:51.000
[Music]
00:59:03.000
[Music]
00:59:05.000
[Music]