table of contents

03/27/2014

“How Old are We?” — A Monologue

download transcript [vtt]
00:00:00.000
[ Music ]
00:00:07.000
This is KZSU Stanford.
00:00:09.600
Welcome to entitled opinions.
00:00:12.240
My name is Robert Harrison.
00:00:14.260
We're coming to you from the Stanford campus.
00:00:17.680
[ Music ]
00:00:30.000
That's right.
00:00:35.000
This is Robert Harrison finally coming back to you from the netherworld
00:00:39.000
of the KZSU studios here on the Stanford campus.
00:00:43.000
After a long, long hiatus.
00:00:46.000
It's been a good nine months since our last confession.
00:00:50.000
And I know that for some of you it has been a terrible drought,
00:00:54.000
a drought of the intellectual sort,
00:00:56.000
which can be almost as depressing and devastating
00:01:00.000
as the meteorological drought we've been living through
00:01:04.000
or dying through here in California for the past two years.
00:01:08.000
If you've missed the life-giving reigns of entitled opinions,
00:01:13.000
I feel your pain.
00:01:15.000
Some of us have a constitutive need for cloud cover,
00:01:19.000
precipitation, perturbation, some kind of weather activity
00:01:24.000
in order to keep our souls alive.
00:01:27.000
And when you wake up to the same old, sterile blue sky day in and day out,
00:01:33.000
it's a little more than enough to make a man throw himself away.
00:01:37.000
If I may borrow a verse from Comrad, Jimmy Hendrix's song,
00:01:41.000
"Burning of the Midnight Lamp."
00:01:44.000
Speaking of the Midnight Lamp,
00:01:46.000
I've been burning it a lot since we last talked,
00:01:49.000
and I still am,
00:01:51.000
but I've heard your pleas, you suffering ones.
00:01:54.000
So here I am with Dylan Montanari still at my side,
00:01:58.000
ready to bring your field some relief
00:02:01.000
with a brand new season of entitled opinions.
00:02:05.000
[music]
00:02:09.000
[music]
00:02:13.000
[music]
00:02:17.000
[music]
00:02:21.000
[music]
00:02:25.000
[music]
00:02:31.000
[music]
00:02:35.000
[music]
00:02:41.000
[music]
00:02:47.000
[music]
00:02:49.000
Today's show isn't really the start of our official season
00:02:52.000
because we haven't applied for a slot on KZSU.
00:02:55.000
That's going to be another week or two.
00:02:57.000
And what I have in mind today is to welcome you all back,
00:03:01.000
share some thoughts with you about some previous shows,
00:03:06.000
and give you an idea of what you can expect in the upcoming season.
00:03:10.000
We have shows planned on F. Scott's Fitzgerald,
00:03:15.000
Leo Tolstoy, Dostoyevsky,
00:03:18.000
Greek myth science and religion existentialism,
00:03:22.000
and Saint Perpetua, my favorite,
00:03:25.000
just to mention a few.
00:03:28.000
But today I want to take the occasion to remark that back in August,
00:03:33.000
we reposted a show that went back to our very first season,
00:03:37.000
one of the first shows we did on this program with Stanford cosmologist,
00:03:43.000
Professor Andre Linde, on the inflationary cosmos.
00:03:49.000
And in my monologue to that show,
00:03:53.000
I quoted Ralph Waldo Emerson's essay experience,
00:03:59.000
which opens with a simple question,
00:04:02.000
"Where do we find ourselves?"
00:04:05.000
And I claim in that monologue that the most primordial place
00:04:10.000
to begin answering it is to take stock of where we find ourselves
00:04:15.000
in the cosmological order of things.
00:04:20.000
The answer to that question is not a stable or constant one.
00:04:24.000
When Dante was writing his divine comedy in the 1300s,
00:04:28.000
the universe was a very different kind of place than it is today,
00:04:32.000
a very beautiful place actually.
00:04:34.000
Love, move the sun and the other stars in great concentric circles.
00:04:40.000
The heavenly spheres were nestled into one another,
00:04:43.000
and the whole was sublimely finite and self-contained,
00:04:49.000
as well as eternal.
00:04:51.000
Then came the Copernican Revolution and Pascal's post- Copernican dread,
00:04:58.000
expressed by that thought of his,
00:05:00.000
where he says, "The eternal silence of these infinite spaces terrifies me."
00:05:05.000
And a few hundred years after that came the brave new world
00:05:09.000
of Einstein's general relativity,
00:05:12.000
which once again overturned the whole picture,
00:05:15.000
and time and space became fused in ways
00:05:19.000
that are still incomprehensible to the average person.
00:05:22.000
And I include myself among those average people.
00:05:25.000
But it didn't stop there.
00:05:27.000
In the last hundred years at brave new universe,
00:05:30.000
as undergone significant metamorphoses as well,
00:05:33.000
and it's no longer what it was just a century ago.
00:05:38.000
Now back in 2005, when I had Andre Linde on this show,
00:05:43.000
we talked about his theory,
00:05:45.000
or he being one of the major proponents of the theory
00:05:48.000
of the inflationary universe, namely,
00:05:50.000
that our universe began with a huge expansion
00:05:56.000
of space from a subatomic particle through a process known as inflation,
00:06:05.000
which he then went on to explain in terms
00:06:10.000
that I believe all of us can understand on that show.
00:06:13.000
And that's why back in August,
00:06:16.000
we reposted it so that it would not lie their buried
00:06:21.000
and lost in our archives.
00:06:23.000
Now, the funny thing is that Andre Linde has come back
00:06:26.000
into the news big time in the last ten days, two weeks,
00:06:32.000
because on Monday, March 17, 2014,
00:06:39.000
there had been a breakthrough observational breakthrough
00:06:43.000
down in the South Pole,
00:06:46.000
where a group of astronomers and scientists
00:06:50.000
led by Harvard's Smithsonian Center's John Colvac,
00:06:56.000
made an astonishing discovery
00:06:59.000
that seems to confirm the theory
00:07:03.000
of the inflationary cosmos
00:07:06.000
that my guest, Andre Linde,
00:07:09.000
was giving an explanation of some nine years ago.
00:07:14.000
What they discovered was the so-called gravitational wave
00:07:19.000
and I'll read you from the New York Times article on it.
00:07:24.000
These gravitational waves would be the signature
00:07:27.000
of a universe being wrenched violently apart
00:07:32.000
when it was roughly a trillionth of a trillionth of a trillionth
00:07:36.000
of a second old.
00:07:38.000
These gravitational waves are the long-sought smoking gun evidence
00:07:43.000
of inflation.
00:07:45.000
Linde was expressing the hope that in some kind of distant future
00:07:51.000
and I don't think he ever expected it to be within his own lifetime,
00:07:54.000
but in some distant future,
00:07:56.000
there would be empirical, experimental proof of the theory of inflation.
00:08:03.000
Even though inflation has been around for 35 years,
00:08:08.000
many people in Cruelling, Linde really wondered
00:08:11.000
whether it could ever be proved.
00:08:13.000
Now, if these results of Dr. Kovacs' team are corroborated,
00:08:20.000
then as the New York Times puts it,
00:08:23.000
it will stand as a landmark in science comparable
00:08:26.000
to the recent discovery of dark energy pushing the universe apart
00:08:30.000
or of the big bang itself.
00:08:32.000
It would leave open vast realms of time and space
00:08:36.000
and energy to science and speculation.
00:08:40.000
Confirming inflation would mean that the universe we see,
00:08:45.000
extending 14 billion light years in space
00:08:49.000
with its hundreds of billions of galaxies,
00:08:53.000
is only an infinitesimal patch in a larger cosmos
00:08:58.000
whose extent, architecture and fate are unknowable.
00:09:03.000
Moreover, beyond our own universe,
00:09:07.000
there might be an endless number of other universes bubbling
00:09:12.000
into fro the eternity,
00:09:14.000
like a pot of pasta water boiling over.
00:09:18.000
So where do we find ourselves in the cosmos
00:09:21.000
on a planet called Earth in a solar system,
00:09:24.000
where the planet's revolving around one star
00:09:27.000
that belongs to some remote provincial part of the Milky Way,
00:09:32.000
which is our galaxy.
00:09:33.000
A galaxy contains billions of stars,
00:09:37.000
hundreds of billions of stars in average galaxy,
00:09:40.000
and we know that there are hundreds of billions of galaxy
00:09:43.000
in our observable universe alone.
00:09:46.000
And now, if indeed the discovery of gravitational waves
00:09:51.000
is proven true, we find that perhaps what we know
00:09:55.000
as our universe is itself nothing but a speck
00:09:59.000
in a provincial realm of a much larger multi-universe.
00:10:02.000
So do we find ourselves anywhere that we can locate
00:10:07.000
in terms of coordinates that make us give us a sense of orientation?
00:10:12.000
I really don't know.
00:10:13.000
This is something that is going to have a call on us
00:10:16.000
to have a serious reckoning with exactly where we orient
00:10:21.000
ourselves in this brave new world of an inflationary cosmos.
00:10:25.000
Andre Linde, if you want to re-listen to that show,
00:10:28.000
as I mentioned, we've been reposted it,
00:10:30.000
but he's also been quoted a lot in the news,
00:10:33.000
and there's also videos of him learning the news
00:10:36.000
of this recent discovery that you might want to check out
00:10:39.000
on YouTube and other venues for that.
00:10:42.000
But today what I'd like to do is ask the same question,
00:10:45.000
where do we find ourselves from another point of view,
00:10:47.000
which is not where do we find ourselves in space,
00:10:50.000
but where do we find ourselves?
00:10:52.000
That's called in time.
00:10:54.000
But not that huge cosmological time of 14 billion years,
00:10:58.000
but I think that for a sense of orientation
00:11:01.000
for human beings, we have to know where we find ourselves
00:11:05.000
in the historical time in which we live.
00:11:09.000
And that means that we have to answer a simple question,
00:11:14.000
which really has no simple answer,
00:11:16.000
which is how old are we?
00:11:19.000
We'll take a quick break here and be right back with you.
00:11:23.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:11:28.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:11:57.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:12:00.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:12:04.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:12:08.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:12:12.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:12:16.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:12:20.000
[MUSIC PLAYING]
00:12:49.000
So what I'd like to do in the rest of this opening monologue
00:12:53.000
of our 10th season is ask the same question,
00:12:57.000
where do we find ourselves from the point of view,
00:12:59.000
not of where we find ourselves in space,
00:13:02.000
but where we find ourselves in time?
00:13:04.000
And when we talk about human beings finding themselves
00:13:08.000
in time, what we mean above all is where do we find ourselves
00:13:12.000
in history?
00:13:14.000
At what point in an ongoing history are we located?
00:13:18.000
And that requires us to ask a simple question, which actually
00:13:23.000
has no simple answer, which is just how old are we?
00:13:28.000
And I mean we who in 2014 belong to the cultural age
00:13:35.000
or historical age that is presently getting underway,
00:13:40.000
and which is different than the historical age of even 20
00:13:46.000
years ago.
00:13:47.000
To raise the question of age, we have to keep in mind
00:13:55.000
that nothing in the universe be it the newborn infant
00:14:00.000
or the universe itself is without age.
00:14:05.000
If a phenomenon does not age, it is not of this world,
00:14:08.000
and if it is not of this world, it is not a phenomenon.
00:14:14.000
So we have on the whole, I believe, a very poor understanding
00:14:18.000
of the essence of age, because our intellect evolved
00:14:22.000
to deal more with objects in space rather than with the
00:14:30.000
unfolded intricacies of growth, duration, and accumulation.
00:14:36.000
That's why we probably find it easier to spatialize time
00:14:41.000
to think of time in terms of space, in other words,
00:14:45.000
to think of it as a linear or chronological succession
00:14:49.000
of present moments, then to fathom the multidimensional
00:14:55.000
interpenetrating recesses of age.
00:14:58.000
In fact, we have a stubborn tendency to reduce age to time.
00:15:05.000
And here's the point.
00:15:06.000
What is time, if not a prodigious abstraction?
00:15:11.000
What the medieval is called a flatus vochis,
00:15:14.000
just a breath of air that's pronounced by the voice
00:15:17.000
that is empty of content.
00:15:20.000
Only age gives time a measure of reality.
00:15:25.000
And we shouldn't allow ourselves to be fooled by the fact
00:15:29.000
that even the most sophisticated philosophers think of age
00:15:33.000
as a function of time.
00:15:37.000
A phenomenological analysis reveals instead
00:15:42.000
that we really should think of time as a function of age.
00:15:47.000
After all, any concept we may have of time, ages,
00:15:53.000
and is subject to an aging process.
00:15:57.000
Hence our concept of time today, in the twenty-first century,
00:16:01.000
it's not at all what it was for the ancients.
00:16:06.000
Now the same holds true for eternity,
00:16:09.000
which shares in the general mortality of phenomena.
00:16:13.000
Eternity no longer appears to us as it did to Plato,
00:16:17.000
for example, when he and his fellow Greeks turn their gaze
00:16:21.000
to the stars.
00:16:23.000
Nor does it appear to us as it did to Dante
00:16:26.000
when he and his fellow Christians turn their gaze
00:16:30.000
to the celestial spheres.
00:16:33.000
In fact, eternity has been largely dissociated
00:16:36.000
from our dynamic, ever-expanding, and mortal cosmos.
00:16:40.000
We now believe that the cosmos had a beginning
00:16:43.000
and that it will have an end.
00:16:45.000
Hence eternity has largely disappeared from our phenomenological horizons.
00:16:50.000
The timelessness of eternity has grown old.
00:16:53.000
You could put it that way.
00:16:55.000
The timelessness of eternity has grown old.
00:16:58.000
And for all intents and purposes has aged itself out of existence.
00:17:04.000
Now in his book Creative Evolution,
00:17:09.000
the evolution of the first century of the first century,
00:17:12.000
published in 1907, the French philosopher,
00:17:16.000
Auree Bechson, exposed in a very compelling fashion,
00:17:20.000
traditional philosophies, blind tendency
00:17:24.000
to conceive of time geometrically rather than organically.
00:17:30.000
Yet for all of Bechson's deep thinking about La Juree,
00:17:33.000
as he calls it, "juration," and "organic form,"
00:17:38.000
Bechson never really put forward a philosophy of age.
00:17:41.000
He offered merely another philosophy of time,
00:17:45.000
one founded on biological rather than chronological paradigms.
00:17:50.000
That represented a significant corrective and contribution
00:17:53.000
to be sure, yet there's more to the phenomenon of age
00:17:57.000
than biology alone can account for since humans
00:18:01.000
are biological beings who create trans-biological institutions
00:18:06.000
that put cultural and historical elements into play
00:18:10.000
in ways that Bechson, along with most other philosophers,
00:18:14.000
leaves largely unexamined.
00:18:19.000
All living things obey an organic law of growth and decay,
00:18:23.000
and in that respect human beings are not exceptions.
00:18:27.000
According to the riddle of the Sphinx,
00:18:30.000
we walk on four legs in the morning, two legs at noon,
00:18:34.000
and if we live long enough, end up on three legs in the evening.
00:18:40.000
Yet as edipus discovers, after he enters a city of thieves,
00:18:47.000
confident that he has solved the riddle of the Sphinx,
00:18:52.000
there is far more to the story than that.
00:18:55.000
The story begins before birth and continues after death.
00:19:01.000
In other words, unlike other living things,
00:19:04.000
"antropus," man, which is the answer to the riddle of the Sphinx,
00:19:10.000
this antropus is born into humanly created worlds
00:19:15.000
whose historical past and future transcend the individuals biological lifespan.
00:19:23.000
So these worlds, which the Greeks call the police,
00:19:28.000
are founded upon institutional and cultural memory,
00:19:32.000
conferring on their inhabitants a historical age,
00:19:38.000
that is altogether different in nature than biological age.
00:19:44.000
Since no human being lives outside of such worlds,
00:19:48.000
and those worlds all come with their legacies and traditions,
00:19:51.000
we could say that humans are heterochronic in their age.
00:19:56.000
Now, what does that mean?
00:19:58.000
Heterochronic.
00:19:59.000
It means that they possess many diverse kinds of ages,
00:20:05.000
all bound up together.
00:20:08.000
Biological age, historical age, institutional age,
00:20:13.000
psychological age, and so forth.
00:20:16.000
So by and by, we can see how these various ages intersect with one another,
00:20:22.000
both in individuals and in civilizations.
00:20:25.000
At these various ages intersect with one another,
00:20:28.000
both in individuals as well as in civilizations.
00:20:33.000
So we can note here for the record that once antroposa arrives on the scene,
00:20:39.000
the phenomenon of age increases in complexity,
00:20:43.000
at least as much as it did when life first gained a foothold on our planet.
00:20:48.000
Now, the one thinker from whom one would have expected a very compelling philosophy of age,
00:20:54.000
especially as it relates to the human component,
00:20:58.000
is our old friend Martin Heidegger,
00:21:01.000
who devoted a number of shows to Martin Heidegger here on this program.
00:21:05.000
Heidegger thought more radically about time
00:21:08.000
than any philosopher before or after him.
00:21:12.000
Yet he too, like the metaphysical tradition that he strive to overcome,
00:21:17.000
had very little to say about age.
00:21:21.000
And this is quite surprising because Heidegger is the thinker who taught us that time
00:21:27.000
is ostensive.
00:21:30.000
In other words, that time is a kind of movement,
00:21:34.000
Henaseus in Greek, that allows the phenomenon to appear
00:21:39.000
and be taken up by the perceiver in thought as well as in word.
00:21:47.000
Heidegger also taught us that times,
00:21:51.000
the "sclosive dynamism" has its source in designs finite temporality,
00:21:58.000
which is his way of referring to a human existence fundamental mortality.
00:22:08.000
Now, why he made no effort to link human temporality to human age,
00:22:15.000
even in the straightforward sense of the stages of life,
00:22:18.000
is hard for me to fathom,
00:22:21.000
for when it comes to designs existential determinations, as he calls him,
00:22:27.000
age remains as fundamental as "throneness projection, fallenness, being under death and being with others."
00:22:37.000
Those of you who have read "being in time" will recognize these fundamental existentially.
00:22:45.000
Fundamental determinations of human design.
00:22:49.000
Yet in being in time, as well as in Heidegger's later thought,
00:22:53.000
design remains essentially ageless.
00:22:59.000
Now, the reason I find this surprising is because one could say that age is to time what place is to space.
00:23:08.000
Nowhere in his corpus is Heidegger more compelling than when he reveals how place in its situated boundedness is more primordial than space.
00:23:18.000
In an exemplary phenomenological fashion, he shows us how the scientific concept of homogeneous space derives from,
00:23:28.000
or is made possible by designs disclosure of the "there", the "dah" of its situated being.
00:23:39.000
That's why when we ask, where do we find ourselves in the cosmos,
00:23:42.000
and we realize that that cosmos is getting huge or investor all the time, and that it becomes essentially impossible to measure our place in it.
00:23:52.000
Because the scale keeps growing exponentially.
00:23:57.000
The fact of the matter is that if Heidegger is right, our "dah", our openness here, where we disclose the place of our habitation that without our human presence to disclose the place,
00:24:11.000
where the cosmos reaches us, there would be no phenomenological cosmos per se.
00:24:19.000
It all depends on this original disclosure of the being of entities.
00:24:25.000
So with such a compelling analysis of the primordiality of place over space,
00:24:33.000
one would have expected from Heidegger a similar analysis of how age in its existential and historical dimensions figures as the source of designs finite temporality,
00:24:48.000
and with it of the chronologically governed concept of time,
00:24:53.000
This analysis of that sort would have given Heidegger the occasion to show that the constant finishing action of time takes place in and through the unfolding of age, day in and day out, year in and year out, era after era, epoch after epoch.
00:25:10.000
All this may sound very abstract to some of you, but we're talking about what you and I do every moment, every day of our lives, which is undergo the aging process.
00:25:22.000
The unfolding of age in its finite limitations.
00:25:27.000
But again, unfortunately, nowhere in his corpus does Heidegger ponder age as this boundary of finitude that allows time in its extensive or showing character to disclose the world of phenomena.
00:25:48.000
So let me briefly attempt here to point out how much goes unaccounted for, phenomenologically speaking when one fails to ground time in age or to derive time from age.
00:26:03.000
And I'd begin by remarking that every phenomenon has its age or better its ages. Why the plural? Because entities become phenomena only where they are perceived intended or apprehended.
00:26:22.000
There are no phenomena in the technical sense of the term where there is no perception, and there is no perception where there is not a sentient perceiver.
00:26:37.000
Hence, if that's the case, the phenomenon, any phenomenon, brings together at least two independent, yet intersecting ages.
00:26:48.000
There's the age of the entity, and then there's the age of the apprehender.
00:26:55.000
So a young boy and his grandfather in an old growth forest of the Pacific Northwest may look on the same giant redwood tree, yet they do not see the same phenomena.
00:27:14.000
At least not exactly the same phenomena. Because of their age difference, it appears one way to the boy and another way to his elder.
00:27:28.000
The sky that I see today is more or less the same blue spectacle it always was, yet it's not the same sky of old.
00:27:41.000
When I was seven years old, it was my body's covenant with the cosmos. By twenty, it became the face of an abstraction. Today it's the dome of a house. I know I will not inhabit for too much longer.
00:27:58.000
Shortly it will be the answer to what today still remains a question. Now it does no good to say that I project my age onto phenomena.
00:28:07.000
That's not what I'm talking about here. The sky has always appeared to me as something ageless, yet its agelessness appears differently as I age. My only access to the sky and to the world of phenomena in general is from within my own non-solestual age.
00:28:29.000
If by identity we mean self-seminous through time, and that's the conventional definition of identity, self-seminous through time, then I would say that age is the latent element that introduces a differential into identity's equation, hence into the appearance of things.
00:28:53.000
To express the same thought in slightly different terms, I do not lend the phenomenon my age rather the phenomenon reaches me through the forms of reception and perception that pertain to my age.
00:29:08.000
Historical age also inflicts the appearance of the phenomenon, but we'll leave that aside for the moment. One other way of putting what I'm talking about here is, and here I'm using a Kantian language, we could say that time is not the same.
00:29:22.000
It's not the same form of intuition in childhood as it is in adulthood, or it's not the same form of intuition in antiquity as it is in early modernity, as it is in late modernity.
00:29:40.000
Or we could also say that the imagination schematizes differently in youth than it does in old age, and those of you who know your Emmanuel Kant will understand the subtext here of what I've just said.
00:29:57.000
Now, if philosophers, including Heidegger, have failed to bring proper consideration to bear on the phenomenon of age, that is really not the case with poets.
00:30:11.000
Where philosophers have deserted us, the poets really come to our rescue. And I believe that in some ways the whole history of poetry is a sustained confrontation and coming to terms with the mysteries, depths, recesses, and enigmas of age in all of its aspects.
00:30:36.000
Gerard Manley Hopkins, early 20th century poet, let me invoke him as an example.
00:30:46.000
He has a poem, a pretty well-known poem, he's called "Spring and Fall," where an older speaker addresses a young girl, and gives poetic expression to what I have been talking about more prosaically about
00:31:05.960
the age differential in the phenomenon self-manifestation.
00:31:10.960
So here's Hopkins poem "Spring and Fall."
00:31:14.960
Margaret, are you grieving over golden grove, unleaving?
00:31:20.960
Leaves like the things of man, you with your fresh thoughts care for, can you?
00:31:28.960
As the heart grows older, it will come to such sights colder, by and by, nor spare a sigh, the world of one would leaf me a lie.
00:31:40.960
And yet you will weep and know why.
00:31:45.960
Now no matter child the name, sorrows, springs are the same, nor mouth had, no nor mind expressed what heart heard of, ghost, guest.
00:31:58.960
It was the "Black Man was born for," it is Margaret you mourn for.
00:32:10.960
Personally I find that Margaret's emotions here lack a certain credibility.
00:32:16.960
Young girls do not typically shed tears over the falling of autumn leaves, but that's really irrelevant because the poem draws attention to two important phenomenological facts that have nothing to do with the emotional credibility of the scene.
00:32:34.960
The first such fact is that the aging process affects changes in the phenomenon's perception.
00:32:42.960
The second is that perception is, at some level, at least with human beings, always a self-perception.
00:32:53.960
Why do I say that?
00:32:55.960
Because the difference between the child and the adult in this poem is that the adult presumably knows why he weeps, while
00:33:04.920
Margaret presumably does not.
00:33:07.920
She has yet to understand that "sorrows springs are the same."
00:33:15.920
Now that last assertion may in fact be dubious or even downright false, sorrows springs are not always the same.
00:33:25.920
I believe.
00:33:27.920
Again, the truth of Hopkins poem lies not in its propositional claims, but in its revelation that as the heart grows older, the same phenomenon accrues a different meaning, a meaning intimately bound up with the age of the perceiver.
00:33:49.920
The Italian poet Giacomo Leopardi, early 19th century poet,
00:33:55.920
he also held that things appear differently to perception with age.
00:34:00.920
In his very pessimistic worldview, youth has a tendency to see infinite promise in the phenomenon of nature.
00:34:11.920
Autumn leaves, moonlight, the open sea.
00:34:14.920
These are intimations of future happiness.
00:34:19.920
By inviting youth to experience its beauty in the mode of promise, nature, he claims, is unspeakably cruel, since that promise is and always was only an ingan or a deception.
00:34:37.920
As he puts it in his poem, "Acelvia, unatura, unatura, perchenon, rendi, poi, quel, quepromet, d'allore, percet, d'itant, d'ohingan, nie, vie, t'ohoy."
00:34:51.920
Oh, nature, oh, nature, why do you not deliver on what you promised back then?
00:34:57.920
Why do you deceive your children, so?
00:35:02.920
So, in Hopkins case, age reveals in time the implicit truth naively perceived in the phenomenon by a young girl.
00:35:12.920
In Leopardi's case, it reveals in time the deception that was implicit in the naive perception of youth.
00:35:20.920
Again, neither one nor the other vision need be empirically true.
00:35:26.920
What's important, at least for our purposes, is that unlike the history of philosophy, the history of poetry offers an abundance of phenomenological insight into the way truth reveals itself in and through the unfolding of age.
00:35:46.920
We'll be right back.
00:35:48.920
[Music]
00:36:08.920
What's the word in a golden cage, on a winter's day in the rain?
00:36:24.920
Why better than a golden cage, alone?
00:36:40.920
The leaves blow across the long black road to the dark and sky in its range, but the white bird just sits in her cage unknown.
00:37:09.920
When the bird must fly, she will die.
00:37:33.920
[Music]
00:37:49.920
If time is discolusive of truth, which is what hider claims, and if truth in turn is age bound as I claim, then what is absolutely true at one stage of life,
00:38:02.920
is at best only, relatively true at another.
00:38:08.920
So, for example, when I first read the opening verses of T.S. Eliot's The Four Quartets many years ago, I had no doubts that I had stumbled upon the timeless truth of time itself.
00:38:22.920
Like quote, "Time present and time past are both perhaps present in time future and time future contained in time past.
00:38:34.920
If all time is eternally present, all time is unredeemable.
00:38:40.920
What might have been is an abstraction remaining a perpetual possibility only in a world of speculation."
00:38:51.920
So, if you assume, as I did back then, that whatever goes unrealized falls away into oblivion, then Eliot's lines about the might have been resound with an ominous or accurate truth.
00:39:11.920
It puts enormous pressure on you when you take seriously Nietzsche's doctrine of the eternal return of the same, namely that every moment that we live in our lives we are fated to repeat.
00:39:28.920
And this time eternally puts enormous pressure on what you do with every moment when you assume that there is going to be an infinite repetition of that same moment.
00:39:44.920
And I would say that it puts almost equal pressure on you if you take Reilke, Reiner Reilke, the Austrian poet at his word, when he writes in the ninth elegy of his of his doingo-elegies, he says, "Us meaning human beings, the most fleeting, once everything only once, once and no more."
00:40:11.920
We too, once, never again.
00:40:18.920
Both these theses, eternal return, and the once only sympathize with one another in that both affirm realities, consummation in the Reil, but reality consumes itself in the Reil.
00:40:36.920
I'm happy to concede that there's a certain truth to that proposition.
00:40:43.920
However, I believe that it holds far more sway over a young person than it does over an older person, if only because the former, the young person, feels under much greater imperative to realize his or her potential, then does an older person whose life for better or for worse.
00:41:05.920
Has already, has already, has already reached a kind of narrative conclusion, even if it has not yet reached a biological end.
00:41:16.920
I do believe that the Reil shines forth as the crown of the possible.
00:41:24.920
However, I am no longer convinced as I was when I first read Eliot's lines from the Four Quartets that the possible finds this redemption only in actualization.
00:41:37.920
Maybe that's because I've arrived at an age where the relation between time and reality has undergone a shift that makes me more prone to believe that the punctuality of our lived moments are more like sparks,
00:41:53.920
arising from and returning to that indeterminate source of all being which an axamander, pre-socratic Greek philosopher called the "appeton", the unbounded matrix, the boundless chaos sometimes is translated.
00:42:16.920
This "appeton" is not nothingness, nor is it an abstraction remaining a perpetual possibility only in a world of speculation, as Eliot puts it.
00:42:29.920
It's overbearing potentiality, the "appeton" is overbearing potentiality penetrates the phenomenon and gives it depth, density, and opacity.
00:42:42.920
Given my heightened awareness of this excess of potentiality never to be actualized in reality, there's always an excess of potentiality.
00:42:56.920
I would say that the phenomenon becomes suffused by this latent potentiality and it adds to the actual wonder of the phenomenon itself.
00:43:10.920
The phenomenon gains a thick and recessive penumbra, and I could put the same thought differently by saying that this vast ocean of potentiality on which actuality drifts like a single glass wave gives buoyancy and depth to our experience of the real.
00:43:33.920
I hate to say that there are further complexities at work in the phenomenon of age, especially when it comes to its human inflections.
00:43:41.920
If I say I am 59 years old, that is an empirical fact, but what exactly does that mean?
00:43:51.920
Who or what is this "I"?
00:43:55.920
Is it a body, a mind, a soul, or an aggregate of the three?
00:44:02.920
Even if, for the sake of argument, we call it only a body, we are still not dealing with a simple sum.
00:44:10.920
My body is at once 59 years old and several billion years old, since all of its atoms originated a few seconds after the Big Bang, hence our as old as the universe itself.
00:44:27.920
Here we go back to our friend, Andre Linde, and why it's so important to know what happened at the moment of the Big Bang, because every atom in our body originated right at that moment.
00:44:45.920
So I am 59 years old plus 14 billion years old in my body.
00:44:53.920
Moreover, you could say that a body does not age uniformly in all of its parts.
00:44:59.920
The age of a weak heart is not that of a sound kidney.
00:45:03.920
One can turn old in one part of the body and stay young in another over the course of years.
00:45:11.920
John Banville, the Irish novelist, wrote a novel called "Shroud", where the protagonist of that novel,
00:45:22.920
who is living in Turin, remarks the following about his Italian neighbors, "They age from the top down for these are still the legs they must have had in their 20s or even earlier."
00:45:41.920
And that's true.
00:45:44.920
Legs have a tendency to remain much more constant through time than other parts.
00:45:52.920
We age really from the top down.
00:45:55.920
That became very apparent to me when I went to see the Rolling Stones about a year or two ago in the San Jose Arena,
00:46:01.920
and the Stones in their legs, they looked just as same ages they always were in their 20s,
00:46:09.920
from the top down that the aging process begins.
00:46:13.920
One way or another, the body as a body is also heterochronic in nature.
00:46:20.920
In other words, it has many ages.
00:46:22.920
Now, my body contains a brain.
00:46:26.920
Is my brain the same age as my mind? Surely not.
00:46:31.920
For unlike the brain, the mind is linked by affiliation and inheritance to other minds, past and present.
00:46:40.920
W.B. Yates writes in his poem, "A Prayer for My Daughter."
00:46:45.920
"My mind, because of the minds that I have loved, the sort of beauty that I have approved, prosper but little, has dried up of late."
00:46:57.920
Like Yates, I have loved minds as old as an axamander and Plato.
00:47:03.920
That makes my mind whose thought is informed by theirs over 2,000 years old.
00:47:09.920
Whether that makes it older or younger than my brain is anybody's guess.
00:47:15.920
As for my soul, or what used to be called the soul before it curled up and disappeared from history,
00:47:24.920
I am at least as old as Moses, Homer, or Dante, whose legacy is formed part of my psychic cell-food.
00:47:33.920
And if I am ever reduced to searching the depths of my unconscious, I will most likely find that I am also as old as the prehistoric archetypes of ancient myth.
00:47:47.920
So, the year is 2014. Do I, or this composite that attaches to my first-person singular?
00:47:56.920
Do I belong to my historical age?
00:48:00.920
Well, I am not sure.
00:48:03.920
Certainly, there is more 19th century than 21st century in my temperament.
00:48:08.920
More celestial spheres than general relativity in my projected universe.
00:48:14.920
More ancient Athens than worldwide webs in my cultural geography.
00:48:21.920
Conversely, when I considered how mired civilization still is in the swamps of adovisms,
00:48:30.920
and how snail, slow, we still are as a species in our efforts to get beyond the miseries and follies of the past
00:48:39.920
and realize the promise of modernity, then I feel that historically I am not yet born that I am 59 minus a century or two.
00:48:52.920
Yet for all this untimeliness of mine, I can't deny that I am also a child of my age if only because I cannot fully belong to a world that does not include the likes of radio hit.
00:49:07.920
Now to say that age is relative is to understate and maybe even to misstate the issue.
00:49:12.920
Certainly, once lived experience of age is relative to one's race, class, gender, culture, nation, education.
00:49:25.920
In certain societies, a 15-year-old boy can hardly imagine what it means to be a 15-year-old girl in that same society,
00:49:33.920
or what it means to be a boy of his age in a very different society.
00:49:40.920
Beyond these special relativities, however, there is a more general relativity whereby being 15 years old means something altogether different at the dawn of the third millennium than it did at the dawn of the second or first millennium to say nothing of prehistory.
00:50:02.920
But be it special or general relativity in its basic concept can only take us so far when it comes to the complex manifold that constitutes a person's true age.
00:50:14.920
I mean the manifold of body, mind, and soul, each of which has an unfolded, complicated, dynamic of its own.
00:50:27.920
So the concept of relativity does as much to obscure as to clarify the bewildering nexus that keeps this manifold mysteriously united in a single person, even as it remains in a state of constant flux unfolding its unity in what we call vaguely enough time.
00:50:53.920
Now the human nexus in question is always bound to a first-person singular.
00:51:01.920
That means you and me or you or me.
00:51:07.920
It's a first-person singular, as I mentioned earlier, is born into a given historical era.
00:51:17.920
One could say that history funnels itself through the first-person singular.
00:51:24.920
Historical eras in turn, talking about early modernity, late modernity, middle ages,
00:51:34.920
these historical eras unfold within a larger framework of what have traditionally been called cultural ages.
00:51:43.920
The ancients, for example, spoke of a golden age, a silver age, a bronze age, and so forth.
00:51:49.920
Jambati Stavico, one day we have to do a show on him.
00:51:53.920
We will.
00:51:55.920
Vico spoke of an age of gods, the age of heroes, and the age of men.
00:52:01.920
What's interesting about Vico is that for him the phenomenon's appearance remains bound to a society's cultural age,
00:52:13.920
which is just as important in that respect as an individual's existential age.
00:52:18.920
In other words, as I mentioned before, the changes that a society's mentality undergoes in historical time plays a decisive role in how the phenomenon reveals itself,
00:52:30.920
which confirms my contention that if time is as close of truth, as high to remain tamed, and if truth in turn is age bound as I, along with Vico maintain,
00:52:47.920
then what is true at one stage of life, or at one stage of history, is at best only partially true at another.
00:52:59.920
In other words, even truth has its age, or better its ages.
00:53:14.920
This topic about the philosophy of age, of course, is a much longer story than we have time to cover today.
00:53:21.920
I've just given you a few thoughts that will continue to develop maybe on further shows, but those of you who are interested will have the opportunity in the fall to read all about it in a new book of mine that's coming out with the University of Chicago Press, called "Jouvenessence, a cultural history of our age."
00:53:44.920
And some of what I said, in fact much of what I said comes from the opening section of that first chapter, so you might want to get your hands on that, but we'll be reminding you of its appearance in the fall when we come back on entitled opinions.
00:54:01.920
But since I ended by saying that truth is always partial and continues unfold with our age and time, we will take this monologue for just the partial truth on the philosophy of age.
00:54:16.920
Thanks for listening.
00:54:18.920
We'll be with you shortly in a few weeks with a new season of entitled opinions. I'm Robert Harris.
00:54:25.920
The sun sets gold, and the clouds will fly, and the air turns slow, and the other words I have to always know.
00:54:36.920
And she must fly, she must fly, she must fly, she must fly.
00:54:52.920
[Music]
00:55:21.920
[Music]
00:55:48.920
[Music]
00:56:15.920
[Music]
00:56:42.920
[Music]
00:57:06.920
[Music]
00:57:33.920
[Music]
00:57:35.920
[BLANK_AUDIO]