table of contents

04/16/2019

Simone de Beauvoir with Jeremy Sabol

Jeremy Sabol has taught as a Lecturer in Stanford University’s Program in Structured Liberal Education (SLE) on and off since 2003. Jeremy majored in physics and literature as an undergraduate, then received his Ph.D. in French. His dissertation examined the conceptual role of fiction in Descartes' physics and philosophy, as well as the impact of […]

download transcript [vtt]
00:00:00.000
This is KZSU Stanford.
00:00:02.000
[Music]
00:00:12.000
[Music]
00:00:34.000
Question, what do God in this radio program have in common?
00:00:39.000
Answer, if they didn't exist, one would have to invent them.
00:00:44.000
There was a time some 15 years ago when in title opinions didn't exist yet,
00:00:49.000
and over the past 10 months some of you probably worried that it had all come to an end.
00:00:55.000
Yet here we are surging back to life after our prolonged hibernation.
00:01:01.000
It's been quite a while since our last confession, but we're back from the dead now,
00:01:06.000
back to tell you all, we shall tell you all.
00:01:10.000
Wayneeth the world, but the watch holdeth.
00:01:14.000
In title opinions holdeth the vigil.
00:01:17.000
A glimmer of thought in the thoughtless night of the present age.
00:01:22.000
They say that in the gloom the gold gathers the light about it,
00:01:26.000
and it's true as the gloom thickens all around us.
00:01:31.000
The light gathers all the more intently around our little golden bow
00:01:36.000
that shakes against the cold in this bare, ruined choir of a world
00:01:43.000
where the sweet bird sang of late.
00:01:46.000
Well, our bird hasn't stopped singing.
00:01:49.000
[Music]
00:01:54.000
[Music]
00:02:11.000
The solo end of the entitled opinions.
00:02:14.000
[Music]
00:02:30.000
I think it was Voltaire who said if God didn't exist,
00:02:33.000
one would have to invent him.
00:02:35.000
And speaking of existence, today we have a show I've been looking forward to for a long time
00:02:40.000
about one of the major proponents of existentialism, Simon de Beauvoir.
00:02:45.000
Lover or hater, if Beauvoir didn't exist, she would have to be invented.
00:02:51.000
Indeed, if she were here now, I'm sure she would remind us that human existence
00:02:56.000
is always invented in both senses of the word.
00:03:00.000
Inventio and Latin means to find or discover.
00:03:05.000
According to existentialist doctrine, we find ourselves thrown into a
00:03:09.000
world that is not of our own making, but which we have no choice but to assume responsibility for.
00:03:16.000
To exist means to invent, by exercising, or freedom to act.
00:03:22.000
People who shark that freedom are merely bad inventors.
00:03:27.000
Those of you well acquainted with this program know that I am an avowed existentialist,
00:03:33.000
may not be a card-carrying sartrean or Beauvarian,
00:03:37.000
but I do believe that when all is said and done, we have the world we deserve.
00:03:43.000
And that ultimately, we are the authors of our destinies.
00:03:47.000
We do not choose our facticity yet we choose what to make of it.
00:03:52.000
In my version of existentialism, we are responsible for far more than what we assume responsibility for.
00:04:00.000
In short, I believe there is a considerable quotient of bad faith and self-deception in all of us,
00:04:07.000
as individuals, as well as a collective.
00:04:10.000
That's one reason I think Simone de Beauvoir is one of the most important European intellectuals of the post-war period,
00:04:17.000
because she never stopped reminding us of our existential freedom and agency.
00:04:24.000
I have a feeling that my guest today agrees with me about Beauvoir, at least in part.
00:04:30.000
We've been talking about doing this show for quite some time, and I'm delighted to welcome my colleague Jeremy Sable
00:04:36.000
to the program. He is an intellectual historian and specialist of French literature, especially French existentialism.
00:04:43.000
Jeremy received his PhD at Yale and is taught as a lecturer in Stanford University's program in structured liberal education,
00:04:53.000
otherwise known as SLE. Since 2003, he also lectures in Stanford's Master of Liberal Arts program.
00:05:01.000
Jeremy, welcome to entitled opinions.
00:05:03.000
Thanks Robert, I'm glad to be here.
00:05:05.000
Yeah, I'm glad finally we've been talking about this for a few years actually.
00:05:09.000
So from our past conversations, I gather you agree with me that Simone de Beauvoir is not only a major intellectual,
00:05:15.000
but that her thought is as relevant today as it was when she published groundbreaking books, like the Second Sex and the Ethics of Ambigua.
00:05:22.000
And the 40s and 50s. Am I right about that?
00:05:25.000
I think so Robert. I'm a real big fan of Beauvoir.
00:05:29.000
And if I have to think about her importance, first I would just say, you know, the importance of the existentialist in general to our contemporary moment.
00:05:36.000
I think it's really worth saying something about just the emphasis that we have in our own culture today, thinking about freedom and agency,
00:05:46.000
and also worrying about victimhood, about social forces and what do we do about the pressure of social forces?
00:05:53.000
How much freedom do we in fact have with what seems like oppressive social forces all around us?
00:05:59.000
This is just central questions for the existentialist.
00:06:02.000
So I think all of them, the existentialists in general, are really important to us now. It should be important to us now.
00:06:08.000
But Beauvoir in particular, I think Beauvoir thought first and most clearly about how to think about individual freedom given the fact that we're not all socially or politically free.
00:06:20.000
And so I think Beauvoir is especially relevant today for us as we think about those problems.
00:06:26.000
So you would, I suppose, say that Jean-Paul Sast is equally relevant in--
00:06:33.000
I'm just a wonderful, but even more relevant in Europe.
00:06:36.000
Yeah, good. And there's this is kind of one of the things that Sartreans and Beauvoirians fight about.
00:06:43.000
Or only maybe recently, we thought about it. It used to be that one was just a Sartrean and Beauvoir herself was a Sartrean.
00:06:49.000
I think Beauvoir offers some things earlier in her career that Sartreans is struggling to articulate.
00:06:57.000
So on that front, I think that she is the person to look to for some really good formulations of how to think about these problems.
00:07:06.000
But of course, both of them were centrally worried about them, and I like to consider them as they consider themselves to be a team.
00:07:13.000
So I think of their thought really particularly the early work of the late thirties and early forties, where they really came to their first formulations of existentialism.
00:07:23.000
They were working that stuff out together.
00:07:25.000
So are you saying that something like being in nothingness that Sast publishes in '43 or '44?
00:07:33.000
'43.
00:07:34.000
They were a team already when he was working on that book, and that she helps him out?
00:07:39.000
Yes, totally.
00:07:40.000
Yeah, and we have good scholarship on this. I think the scholarship tends to--
00:07:43.000
and for understandable reasons, want to put Beauvoir in the saddle for a lot of the great ideas of being in nothingness,
00:07:50.000
partly because in her own career, both Sartre and Beauvoir in their lifetimes really gave him all the credit for it.
00:07:56.000
So there's this kind of a little bit of a come-up, and there's a little confusion on Beauvoir in part to know why it is that she kind of undersold her own contributions.
00:08:07.000
But we know for a fact now that Beauvoir was working on her first novel, "Lambite" where she came to stay as it's translated into English.
00:08:16.000
That got published in 1943 as well.
00:08:19.000
Beauvoir in working through that novel was reading through a bunch of things, and in the kind of period, right before publication, they were working side by side.
00:08:31.000
But before that, they were separated and writing letters, and Beauvoir's reading Hegel and saying, "You know, you got to read this stuff. It's amazing."
00:08:38.000
Finding really great formulations from Hegel about every self wants the death of the other, these kind of oppositional figures that we see so beautifully conveyed in being in nothingness are this kind of Hegelian formulations that Beauvoir is really finding first and articulating their importance to Sartre.
00:08:56.000
The opening pages of Beauvoir's novel, "Lambite" is in some ways her own formulation of existentialism and are encountered with the other.
00:09:07.000
And it's really just a beautifully concise.
00:09:09.000
I do remind me of that opening.
00:09:11.000
So the main character is kind of an etheater, right? She works in a theater, and she's like on the empty stage, actually don't remember if she's on the, she's like leaving the theater, coming to the theater.
00:09:22.000
And she's talking in the theater, right? A theater is just a wonderful place to talk about being thrown into the world, right? Everything is kind of a prompt, and we adopt roles and of course place themselves or inventions, right?
00:09:34.000
So the meaning of them is pure invention.
00:09:37.000
And so the problem that this narrator encounters just in the few first pages is the kind of the problem of that all human meaning is created, that nothing is out there for us already, that we are thrown into a world without meaning.
00:09:53.000
And that kind of the kind of reef of solipsism problem that Sartre encounters in being in nothingness is also really early on in the novel.
00:10:01.000
And so the idea that he's like, well, is it just me out there or is there anybody else? So a lot of the great moves that are maybe more famous in being in nothingness, both wars working out at the same time, maybe a little bit before, they're sharing back ideas back and forth throughout this period.
00:10:17.000
And in a really exciting way, and it's just thrilling to read the letters.
00:10:21.000
Of course, that idea that we're thrown into a world is a high-degenerian origin, having gone to study with high-degener, or at least was at the same university attending lectures.
00:10:35.000
And this thrownness, big concept in being in time, 1926, thrownness and facticity transcendence, there's a high-degenerian matrix to many of the existentialist concepts there, although it's true.
00:10:50.000
As you mentioned, that the Hegelian notion that the subject wants the death of the other, because there's this conflict, this irresolvable conflict between two subjects, each of which is struggling to objectify the other.
00:11:09.000
And I think some of the most potent passages, or parts of the doctrine of being in nothingness, have to do with these hell-less other people, long-fares, and that does have a Hegelian, not a particularly high-degenerian origin.
00:11:25.000
And I will talk, I think, shortly about how Jean-Paul Satz and perhaps even Bovat, commitment to the Hegelian notion of conflict, inter-subjective conflict, creates this dilemma for them when it comes to trying to articulate why a fully-free existentialist subject must choose the freedom of the other.
00:11:53.000
And it's almost like choosing the good of the other, where human relations are more the question of solidarity than they are of conflict.
00:12:02.000
I think that's a fault line that runs through the whole theory.
00:12:05.000
Yeah, I couldn't agree more.
00:12:07.000
And, Robert, I just got to make a pitch for Bovat's letters here, in 40 and 41, she's reading Hegel.
00:12:13.000
And she's reading Hegel, like Lee would read Harry Potter.
00:12:16.000
She reads the phenomenology in about 10 days, and then she immediately starts in on the logic.
00:12:20.000
Which is not an easy book to plow through.
00:12:23.000
I never made it through.
00:12:24.000
Yeah, it's an impossible book.
00:12:25.000
And she's writing letters to Sart, like twice a day, about how thrilling it is.
00:12:29.000
It's like a James Bond novel to her.
00:12:31.000
And you really feel the excitement of that dialectic and this kind of, what we would think of as a kind of a bleak confrontation of two subjects.
00:12:40.000
For her, this is just thrilling.
00:12:42.000
It's very powerful stuff.
00:12:44.000
So, on the question of freedom, which is one of the existentialists, it's part of our facticity that we are determined by the world that we've been thrown into and we're determined by our gender.
00:12:57.000
Society, social circumstances, but that we also, in our being thrown into situation and circumstances, we also transcend, invariably transcend because human being is a transcendence.
00:13:09.000
Another word for which is freedom. And this idea that is very insistent in Jean-Paul Sartte, that this freedom is a source of anguish for most people because it comes with very heavy burdens of responsibility.
00:13:24.000
And that most of us spend most of our time trying to evade that sense of responsibility and to shield, conceal from ourselves, this kind of groundless freedom that is human existence.
00:13:38.000
Yeah, perfectly said, Robert. And I think here, the language that Beauvoir uses, which I find powerful, her book that she writes before the second sex, the book that she considers her existentialist ethics, a book called The Ethics of Ambiguity.
00:13:54.000
The word ambiguous or ambiguity is Beauvoir's formulation for capturing that we have these two sides to us, right, this facticity and this transcendence.
00:14:04.000
And that they're kind of intention or they don't make sense together. If we talk about the world of facts, there are no freedoms in the world of facts.
00:14:12.000
And that human beings are really this composition, this composite between these two pieces and the danger is that we want to lapse back into facticity, the imminence.
00:14:22.000
And it's this great temptation that we have, not only where there are cells, but we love other people's help, right, we love being turned into an object, right, when we talk about objectification, there's some appeal from the subjects,
00:14:33.000
perspective of getting turned into an object, because there's a solid sin. We don't have to make decisions. We're just, well, I'm a professor, I'm a teacher, I'm a
00:14:44.000
I'm an identity, cultural or otherwise. This is identity politics today. Yes. So go on.
00:14:53.000
And maybe we're diving a little bit into the second sex here, but I think one of the, you know, if we go back to the early 40s and we think about Beauvoir and Sarath, they're not only just literary and philosophical geniuses that have this grand vision of what they want to do in the world, they're also just good old-fashioned kind of cultural rebels, right?
00:15:14.000
They're anti-static quo, they see the interwar period and then World War II and they've taken the moral failures of the French in this period as kind of a result of this kind of bourgeois mentality.
00:15:29.000
So, and I think a lot of the kind of vibrancy of their thought comes out of this rejection of the cultural values around them. And so this leads to a kind of problem for Beauvoir and for Sarath. I think the idea of social identities, these kind of
00:15:43.000
ideas about who we might be, you know, for South, he gives the example of the waiter, you know, that a waiter kind of plays like being a waiter, a waiter is a certain kind of personality and a waiter when you get a job in a French cafe, you try to become that waiter.
00:15:57.000
That's a kind of a platonic ideal of the waiter out there and it's a social identity. And for Sarath and Beauvoir, those social identities are purely bad. They only constrict us.
00:16:07.000
They're their refuges for our bad faith. We run, we cling to them so that we don't have to confront our freedom.
00:16:15.000
And I think this is one of the things that we struggle with in our contemporary moment is we see social identities sometimes as very constraining and even oppressive, but we also find great power in them.
00:16:26.000
And I think, well, let's say, you know, so start wrote a book about anti-Semitism and for him the definition of a Jew is only an anti-Semitic definition.
00:16:36.000
Right, there's no value or power in claiming yourself as a Jew, whereas we all know that not to be the case. There's a lot of cultural identities that even when they're problematic and historical and ambiguous, we see real value in adopting them and claiming them for our own.
00:16:51.000
We want to see some power in the idea of claiming a social identity that doesn't necessarily cut all of our freedom away. And Beauvoir and Sarath are not good in the early formulations of their thought. They're not good about saying why we would want to do that. It just seems only bad to adopt social roles.
00:17:07.000
Yeah, I think I have to say that the analysis of the waiter, which is one of the most famous passages in being in nothing is like, I always found it very frustrating because I think it mistakes identity with a profession.
00:17:24.000
Yes, I don't see why it has to be inauthentic to play a waiter as well as you can play the role of a waiter. And then when you're off work, you are who you are. Your identity is not submissive to your role as a waiter. I think it's a little bit unsatisfying.
00:17:41.000
Unless you take the waiter as an example of how easily we can enter into roles and play roles.
00:17:51.000
Yeah, and I think you're right, Robert. I think there's a weakness there. But I think it's partly historical. I think, you know, Sartz idea of the waiter in 1942 is somebody who when they went home, they were still a waiter.
00:18:02.000
Right, exactly.
00:18:03.000
You know, like the butler that we see, you know, the remains of the day, butler, right, you never shirt that identity.
00:18:09.000
That's true. And I do agree with Simone de Beauvoir even here because the ethics of ambiguity, I think is a brilliant analysis of different ways in which people get stuck in particular, self-identifications.
00:18:22.000
And thereby, abnegating their transcendence that we're always transcend a particular role or a particular profession. But she analyzes, she has a whole typology of the subman, the serious man, the adventurer.
00:18:36.000
Yep.
00:18:37.000
And it's when you actually solidify your identity with one of these roles that bad faith really takes hold of you.
00:18:47.000
Yeah, and how, I mean, what I love about that description in the ethics ambiguity is how compelling it seems to adopt these roles, right?
00:18:57.000
They're very difficult to, it seems easy to say, no, no, no, I'm my own person. I reject those roles.
00:19:03.000
But particularly as you get older and you commit to choices, voluntary choices in your life, those choices can calcinate, right? They can become hardened and, and, and, well, it's true.
00:19:16.000
It's where in, in high diggers being in time, one of the most interesting parts of that book for me is when he speaks about a feeder hole in or repetition and where you have this resolve to be your finitude and your projected under death and you shatter against the possibility of your own death.
00:19:36.000
And somehow that projection that being under death will throw you back upon a series of possibilities that you have inherited or that the past transmits to you for free appropriation.
00:19:50.000
And that freedom to choose your hero as high digger puts it is one where there would be nothing wrong with freely choosing to identify with your Jewish heritage or to choose a hero.
00:20:05.000
And emulate or become a Christian or become whatever the choice may be.
00:20:12.000
My feeling is that it all will sash than see one of the wabad get in trouble by trying to propose norms which would distinguish between what is a good choice authentic choice and not authentic choice.
00:20:26.000
Yeah, great, great. Yeah, and you're right. I think both war and start, particularly in this kind of moment, 43, 44, 45, right around the end of the war.
00:20:34.000
They're really struggling with this. They have this clear idea, this philosophical commitment to the idea that freedom is freedom, right? And so if we choose to deny our freedom, bad faith is a choice, right?
00:20:45.000
We can pretend we're not free that we're a mother, we're a Christian, we're whatever and that defines everything about us and what would make that choice any less authentic than to reject those things.
00:20:58.000
So they have this philosophical position about freedom being an ontological condition of being human. There's no way you can get around it. It's not a choice, it's not a value, it's simply a fact of human life.
00:21:10.000
And then on the other hand, they have this, I think, first cultural attitude that then becomes political stance which is that certain kinds of choices are better than others.
00:21:21.000
And so to fight the Nazis is better than to be a Nazi or to be a collaborator and to reject social norms is better than to embrace them. So why would that be more authentic? Is it just because everybody else is doing the bad one? Is that good enough?
00:21:37.000
And here I think both of them struggle and I think both war is the first to clearly identify what she calls this ethics of ambiguity, which is that, so both start and both war have this language of I'm just going to back up a little bit and talk about the project.
00:21:52.000
They both have this idea that we choose projects. And our projects we might even think of as in a broad Aristotelian sense are kind of means and ends, right? There are things we might do for the sake of other things. Here I am in the studio with you.
00:22:06.000
Why am I doing that? Well, we're friends and we've talked about doing this and why is that? So we could imagine a kind of series of nested choices, nested projects that might go all the way out to the project of our very lives, right?
00:22:18.000
So we're starting both war, believe that this the largest level set of our projects is this kind of unspecified vision of what our life is. And we don't always have a sense of when we chose that or how about how about bringing more thought into the world?
00:22:35.000
Okay, good ideas about sharing. So you know your project Robert. Well, so you're an educator as much as I am. You spent even more time with students committed to this project now. Good. Okay, good. So we've got projects. What makes projects better than other projects? Well, both war says that projects which lead to our ability to live out our freedom concretely indefinitely.
00:23:04.000
definitely, so meaning not a specified thing, but I can act out concretely in the
00:23:09.720
lived world any old way I want is better than projects that don't end up like
00:23:14.560
that. So, for example, if I'm in solitary confinement, if I'm a political
00:23:19.820
prisoner, I'm in solitary confinement, I can choose to characterize my life as a
00:23:24.080
life of political struggle, of mute resistance. I could even commit suicide,
00:23:29.540
maybe. I can't do just any old thing. I can't live out that freedom. I still
00:23:36.560
have the freedom to define my life, define why it is that I'm in prison,
00:23:39.780
decide the meaning of my life, but I can't decide to make myself a really nice
00:23:44.360
breakfast with, you know, ex-fluorant team. I can't do that. And it would be better if I
00:23:51.180
could choose projects in my situation that led to more concrete freedoms that are
00:23:57.820
indefinite to be able to act in any other way. So, those are the good kinds of
00:24:02.480
projects that lead towards open horizons instead of close horizons. And so
00:24:09.280
Bovard just says just upfront, "Hey, this is ethical. One is better than the
00:24:13.280
other. And if we choose for ourselves to shut down our open horizons and choose
00:24:18.120
closed-ended projects, that's a moral failure. And if we cause others to do that,
00:24:23.120
that's evil." So, she's just straight up like that's, there's an ethical system
00:24:27.040
right there. The foundation of that system is freedom and ethical choices fall
00:24:32.340
out of seeing freedom not only as a human fact, but also as a grounding value in
00:24:38.860
the world. Yeah. No, it's true. And I still find that there's something
00:24:44.580
sufistical in the argument that because freedom is an ontological condition,
00:24:51.460
there is a norm for our concrete choices in life which would be making
00:25:00.160
choices that favor freedom rather than, yeah, then the opposite. But, go ahead.
00:25:08.480
Yeah, she's very persuasive when she's analyzing the bad faith of these other
00:25:13.600
types. You know, the subman, the serious man, the bourgeois, this is where
00:25:18.240
Jean-Paul Satt, and the one that they were really quite brilliant because they
00:25:21.880
love being in a tribunal where they themselves were not under accusation,
00:25:28.000
where they were the accusers. Yeah, Robert, and I think the problem that you're
00:25:34.520
talking about, I totally identify with. And it's this moment where there's this
00:25:39.000
kind of social critique which is very appealing, this kind of characterization of
00:25:42.440
bad faith, both of the individual and the social level. And that kind of more
00:25:46.880
philosophically rigorous backdrop to that, that they want to be just really hand in
00:25:53.160
hand. And it seems like they're not totally hand in hand. Right? It seems like,
00:25:56.440
you know, if we think about bad faith being just a cognitive part of human
00:26:02.360
reality, like am I redefining my projects when I'm brushing my teeth or am I
00:26:06.200
lapsing into imminence when I'm brushing my teeth? Well, I'm lapsing into
00:26:10.000
imminence. No big deal, right? I mean, it's just part of cognition that we're not
00:26:13.440
always going to be reinventing ourselves. That for starts not a moral flaw. So
00:26:18.800
when does it become a flaw? When does that kind of cognitive fact about us start
00:26:23.480
to shape our behavior? I think it's when you when you deliberately fail to not
00:26:29.760
only take responsibility for the consequences of your action, but you fail to
00:26:34.200
become aware of the degree to which you have brought about certain
00:26:40.400
circumstances for yourself and for others without full awareness of how they
00:26:46.480
had been chosen without you're being aware of it. That's bad faith. Yeah. It's
00:26:50.680
when you're lying to yourself where you're able to tell yourself that you
00:26:55.160
something that you know is not true and convince yourself of that. Yeah. And
00:27:00.160
here Robert, just because you said it's a nicely just there, I'm just going to
00:27:03.640
remind our listeners when we talk about bad faith kind of casually and I
00:27:08.120
certainly do this all the time, we you know, we tend to talk about it in this
00:27:12.800
sense of the human being being composed of both freedom and
00:27:16.120
facticity, right? Transcendence and and and imminence. And we tend to talk most of
00:27:21.320
the time about bad faith being a a willful lying to ourselves about the fact
00:27:27.760
that we are transcendence, right? We pretend that we are in fact this imminent fact
00:27:32.720
about the world, but it's equally bad faith to forget that we are a thing that we
00:27:38.680
are we have imminence to us, right? And here's here's where we willfully forget
00:27:43.280
our own past, right? We think, oh, we're pure transcendence. I can walk away
00:27:48.520
from the child I had. I can walk away from that life because I'm free to choose.
00:27:53.360
I don't have to take responsibility for that. Right? So that's equally bad
00:27:57.000
faith is to forget that in fact our choices do become facts in the world and we
00:28:01.720
have to own those as equally as we own our freedom. Sure. Jeremy, let's talk a little bit
00:28:07.680
about the second sex, which is the major work that she's known for. And why do
00:28:16.360
you think that's that book had such a powerful resonance when it came out?
00:28:20.760
Yeah. And why is it still a book that everyone should read today? Good. Great.
00:28:25.320
My favorite question, Robert, I think for for many decades the second sex was seen
00:28:32.040
rightly as having an impact, a real impact in the world, a political impact in
00:28:37.240
the world of women's rights. It had an enormous impact in the English-speaking
00:28:42.480
world. I think a bigger impact in the English-speaking world before really the
00:28:46.160
French-speaking world and really all the kind of forerunners in the angophone
00:28:52.200
world of what we now call second wave feminism were very influenced by this text. So
00:28:58.160
the kind of 1950s, 1960s in England and America reading the quickly translated
00:29:05.360
English translation of the second sex had a huge impact on actually the lived
00:29:09.760
experiences of women. So big political impact. And I think we're still living in
00:29:15.000
the wake of that. I think you know they're both the excitement around Cheryl
00:29:19.360
Sandberg's lean in and also the criticisms of it just completely resemble the
00:29:24.320
excitement and the criticisms of the second sex in 1949 and 1950s. I wouldn't put
00:29:30.000
those two books in the same category. I do. I do. I do. I do. I do. I think it's a
00:29:35.440
wonder. Sandberg's book is not quite doesn't have the philosophical heft of the
00:29:40.200
second sex. Well we leave that aside. Okay. But okay. So call it applied
00:29:45.720
existentialism. I do. And I think this is where I think it's impact maybe among
00:29:52.480
French intellectuals. I think some of them saw this. I think Sart himself saw the
00:29:56.440
importance of this book in terms of its philosophical impact. But I think
00:30:00.240
we're still coming to terms with thinking about this book not as a foundational
00:30:05.240
text in kind of European feminism, Western European feminism. We're still
00:30:11.040
struggling with seeing it as a really a book of philosophy. And I think that's
00:30:15.440
really what's most exciting to me about the book in addition to its supreme
00:30:20.240
historical and political impact. I just think it's a book which is really
00:30:24.840
trying to show us how to apply existentialism in a particular area where it
00:30:29.640
seems like existentialism might just not help us. And I think when we first
00:30:34.720
learn about existentialism we see it's immediate kind of thrill and also the
00:30:40.320
burden of it in terms of our individual lives. We see it, oh, I'm making choices and
00:30:45.600
those choices matter. And I'm the only person responsible for those choices. And so
00:30:51.240
they immediate impact of existentialism is always at that kind of individualist
00:30:54.960
level. And very early on in the 40s, you know, everyone said, well this this
00:31:00.240
isn't this sign that I help us with social problems. It's not going to help us
00:31:02.920
think about broad collective issues. So for both water to pick up the the
00:31:09.160
subjugation, the second class status of women all over the world. And throughout
00:31:15.280
time as a broad historical fact, collective fact and say, hey, existentialism's
00:31:21.520
the right way to think about this, that was just an exciting kind of gauntlet thrown
00:31:25.920
down to say that existentialism first of all can attack ethical problems but
00:31:30.080
really collective political problems and it's the right way to do it. I just find
00:31:33.920
that thrilling. So what is her argument in the second sex about women?
00:31:38.840
Great and freedom. Great. Well, first of all, she, she challenges us as existentialists to
00:31:44.720
wonder why it could be that there is such a thing of sexism. So if we think about
00:31:49.440
bad faith as being a choice we can make to let's say I'm a young mother and I
00:31:55.480
want to identify as a mother and that's my social role. That's bad faith on my
00:31:59.640
part. So why would it be that a whole set of people, all women would be
00:32:04.600
somehow more collectively inclined to bad faith than men? That just seems bizarre.
00:32:09.240
So it seems that we are aware of women making choices and women have a social
00:32:15.000
status in the world different than men and it seems like individual choices
00:32:19.640
about bad faith couldn't possibly make sense of that. So,
00:32:23.520
a priori existentialism doesn't bad faith at least, doesn't offer us a way to
00:32:27.760
understand why it would be that women collectively have a second class place in
00:32:33.440
society. So, both of our, it has to then say why why would existentialism help us
00:32:39.800
solve this problem and here's her great insight and I'll tell you, you just
00:32:43.400
have to read the first 17 pages of the book. The whole book is wonderful, but
00:32:47.000
the introduction spells it all out. She says that there are, there's always two
00:32:52.560
things going on. First of all, human beings find deep meaning and satisfaction
00:32:58.600
in transcending, transcendence, reaching beyond ourselves towards these
00:33:04.560
projects, towards these open horizons. That's what human beings are made to do.
00:33:08.160
That's when we're authentic. That feels good to us. All human beings constantly do it.
00:33:13.000
That's what we're put on earth to do. That's what we do whether we want to do it or
00:33:17.000
not. But then we have these social roles and some social roles celebrate
00:33:21.400
transcendent activities in the world in terms of concrete lived out freedoms and
00:33:26.160
some don't. So for, for, sorry, in both of our writing books is a kind of
00:33:31.840
heroic activity of transcending yourself and putting yourself out there in the
00:33:35.360
world and becoming someone new. And in fact, lots of roles that we might
00:33:38.640
traditionally describe as masculine are socially seen as associated with
00:33:44.480
lived freedom, concrete lived freedom. And then there are social roles that are
00:33:48.360
kind of like making the bed and making, making breakfast for the family. And those
00:33:52.960
are roles which I value. But do they lead towards open horizons? Do they open up
00:33:58.240
towards new projects? Well, now you got to kind of do them again tomorrow.
00:34:01.760
Are always the same. So for both war, she characterizes a whole set of activities as
00:34:06.400
kind of mired in imminence. You're never going to transcend. No matter how
00:34:11.880
beautifully you make the bed, you're going to make the bed tomorrow. So what
00:34:16.800
happens when a group of people get assigned roles which are mired in imminence?
00:34:22.280
Well, if they want the social status and the social constellations that go along
00:34:28.920
with those roles, then they need to agree to them. And that's kind of the
00:34:32.200
bad faith choice, right? So I choose to be a mother and maybe I'm giving up some
00:34:36.360
transcendence. But I'm a great mother and I get all the cultural value associated
00:34:41.040
with that. So I get the cultural value. I get the social value. But I'm living in
00:34:45.360
bad faith. So I'm not authentic. But if I'm a guy and I get to be president or a pirate
00:34:52.360
or the writer of great novels and plays and existentialist works of philosophy.
00:34:59.880
Well, then I'm authentically living out my freedom in a philosophically sensible way.
00:35:07.720
And I'm also getting all the social status that goes along with being a male and having a
00:35:11.040
traditional male situation. So for a group of people, even when I am mired in bad faith as
00:35:18.520
a male, I might be still living out roles which might encourage me towards living
00:35:24.320
authentically. Whereas for a one, you got to choose. It's a double mind, right?
00:35:27.960
Either you rebel and you are a yeah, social rebel, you cast off the social roles which
00:35:34.800
define you and then you get none of the solace or social status that goes with those
00:35:38.600
things. But you live authentically or you have to live in bad faith and then you get the
00:35:43.080
social status. You can't have one or the other. You can only have one or the other.
00:35:46.840
You don't get both. So for both war, this is the definition of oppression when you can't
00:35:51.760
live authentically with yourself. When a whole group of people can't be authentic. So to
00:35:57.560
me, that's an exciting way to describe a social phenomenon that's still really grounded
00:36:02.760
in the language of bad faith and authenticity and transcendence. True, however, female
00:36:09.480
facticity is not the same thing as male facticity. No, it's not universal the way Jean
00:36:14.120
Paul Sash would have liked it to be when he speaks about human existence in a non-gendered
00:36:21.480
way. And female facticity requires a rather different approach than male
00:36:30.400
facticity. And here I think that she has to come down against the traditional roles that
00:36:38.600
women have played historically speaking. So much so that she ends up in dieting,
00:36:46.160
is putting it too strong. You say that she indicts motherhood as a choice. Yeah, this is terrible.
00:36:52.040
I mean, it's terrible for those of us that think that mothers are important and do important
00:36:57.120
work in the world. Both war seems very, very against. Because you could say that what could
00:37:03.320
be more transcendent than bringing new life into the world, nourishing a new life because
00:37:07.200
that is what the open horizon is the future and so forth. Men left to themselves their
00:37:13.400
horizons are much narrower insofar as Natality is primarily of the other.
00:37:18.360
Right. Yeah. So you would think just off the cuff, right, that what could be more transcendent
00:37:23.600
than motherhood and also what how great to be a woman in which built into your facticity is
00:37:29.120
this ability of creating new life, right? That just seems like that's amazing, right? That's
00:37:33.000
like the emblem of existentialism itself is that built into our facticity is this power
00:37:38.160
to create an event. It's so symbolically perfect yet no. And what are her reasons? Well,
00:37:47.480
so she goes into this brilliant and maybe infuriating chapter of the second sex about
00:37:53.560
about motherhood. Part of it is that you know, both war describes and here we might accuse her
00:37:58.720
of a little bit of bad faith as well that her own life choices and her own kind of commitments
00:38:03.720
as a person have led her to see motherhood in a really narrow sense and for not to understand
00:38:10.320
that motherhood could be empowering or amazing or existentially profound. But here her now
00:38:16.520
says go something like this. There's really two ways that you might live out the experience
00:38:21.520
of being my mother. The first is that you would see this new life as really being your project
00:38:29.480
as part of your open-ended project of the future and it's all about you, right? It's
00:38:36.720
your project. It's not about this other new life who is in fact their own subject. So this
00:38:41.640
is kind of the steam rolling mother, right, who sees the new life as a way to relive,
00:38:48.520
out, repeat, or reinvent herself at the expense of the transcendence and authenticity of this
00:38:56.680
child. So that seems obviously bad. Then what's the other alternative? Well, to really
00:39:02.600
live vicariously through this new life and to really see yourself as really only an auxiliary
00:39:08.840
to this new life that really the child, the son, the daughter, is the true subject. And
00:39:16.680
I'm the helper as the mother, I'm the one who permits this transcendence to flourish.
00:39:21.440
That also has connections with her characterization of the serious man in the ethics of ambiguity,
00:39:27.960
who says that it's the highway or the bridge, it's whatever I'm working on. That's the
00:39:34.360
transcendent thing and I am bringing that into. That is what I worship is the project
00:39:39.320
or it's the new life, it's the son. I have to say I believe that a lot of the primary
00:39:45.520
narcissism that is socialized out of us when we're kids comes back with the vengeance when
00:39:51.640
some people become parents. We're now in the name of their children, they permit themselves
00:39:57.560
the most atrocious forms of ecotism and self regard where everything can be done, everything
00:40:08.000
can be justified in the name of doing it for one's children.
00:40:11.000
Robert, here, this is where I disagree with Beauvoir and I've got to say, first of all,
00:40:16.840
a lot of what I've been talking about, I've learned from colleagues of ours here at Stanford.
00:40:21.440
So, Lanier Anderson and Laura Whitman, your colleague in French and Italian, both their
00:40:26.760
ideas about Beauvoir really influenced me, so I just want to shout out to them here.
00:40:32.000
And Lanier Anderson and I have gone around on this and he thinks Beauvoir is right about
00:40:37.320
motherhood or that her argument makes sense and I want her and him to be wrong. So, I'm
00:40:42.840
clinging to that. And I kind of wish in my optimism, I wish Beauvoir would have described
00:40:49.440
these two dangers of motherhood as that, as risks, right, the kind of steam rolling of
00:40:55.640
the other and the kind of abasement of the self for the child as being too real dangers
00:41:02.960
in motherhood. But in some ways, aren't they the real dangers in all of our encounters with
00:41:07.520
the other? I mean, so this to me gets back to the old existentialist problem is, can
00:41:12.360
we see of interactions with the other as anything other than a kind of a hostile competition
00:41:20.560
where one has to be subject and one has to be object? Or is there such a thing as collaboration?
00:41:24.600
Is it possible to live for, live with another and have shared projects? Is that possible?
00:41:31.440
So I see Beauvoir's challenge here on the motherhood front as similar to her larger challenge
00:41:38.480
of trying to figure out what it would mean to share projects with others.
00:41:43.440
Yeah, good. So, when it comes to this question of the concrete basis on which one makes decisions
00:41:52.960
and this problem that Jean-Paul Sasht and Beauvoir had, they invoke both of them
00:42:00.560
Kant's categorical imperative, no? Yep. Which is in Kant's articulation of it is that when I'm
00:42:08.960
faced with the choice, I should ask myself if this action that I'm going to commit were to be
00:42:14.480
universalized across all of human society, what would be the consequences? Many of these choices
00:42:19.360
would lead to the complete collapse and undoing of human society if everyone were to murder,
00:42:24.160
if everyone were to steal it so forth. Yeah. And although they don't want to apply it case by case,
00:42:30.320
they do invoke this categorical imperative to, as the basis of human freedom and intersubjective
00:42:38.320
relations, which seems highly problematic to me. So, let me read a passage from the ethics of
00:42:46.080
Andrew Guelly. Okay, great. Where we go back now here to Hegel and she says, "Each consciousness,
00:42:53.120
she's quoting Hegel, each consciousness seeks the death of the other." And indeed, at every moment,
00:42:59.200
others are stealing the whole world away from me. She says, "The first movement is to hate them,
00:43:04.480
but this hatred is naive, and the desire immediately struggles against itself. If I were really
00:43:10.160
everything, there would be nothing beside me, the world would be empty. There would be nothing
00:43:14.880
to possess, and I myself would be nothing. If he is reasonable, the young man immediately
00:43:19.600
understands that by taking the world away from me others also give it to me, since a thing is
00:43:24.480
given to me only by the movement which snatches it away from me, to will that there be being
00:43:31.440
is also to will that there be men by whom and for whom the world is endowed with human
00:43:35.520
significations." Okay. Marjorie Greene was one of the first American philosophers to engage with
00:43:44.720
existentialism. It's actually the near Anderson with whom I did a show on Jean-Paul Sashio,
00:43:49.520
who I love that show. He referred me to this essay of hers, Marjorie Greene, written really
00:43:54.080
contemporaneously almost with the ethics of ambiguity called authenticity and existential virtue.
00:43:59.280
And let me just say what Marjorie Greene, let me quote what she writes here. She says that
00:44:06.320
"There's some uneasiness is felt about this contradiction between the Hegelian objectification
00:44:15.600
war of subjects that someone uneasiness is felt about it even at headquarters, headquarters being
00:44:23.280
Simone in the end." It's evidenced by the extremely crude arguments with which Beauvat has
00:44:28.960
since attempted to dismiss it in ethics of ambiguity. The first few one takes of another that
00:44:34.640
the other consciousness wants to death of mine is naive. She says, "For one at once realizes
00:44:41.680
that, of course, as we all know, if anyone takes anything away from me, he is really giving it to me
00:44:46.720
all the while." This is undoubtedly one of the worst philosophical arguments ever penned, not to mention
00:44:53.120
the shocking fact that there are, in this case, 400 pages of naivety in the master's masterpiece.
00:44:58.000
So, ouch. That does hurt. Especially for an ex, as I said, I'm in a voud existentialist.
00:45:05.440
I still hold to the, you know, the basic arguments, but it's that kind of
00:45:12.640
very French, sophisticated reasoning that what is given to me is actually taken away from me and
00:45:19.840
what's taken away from me is actually given to me where everything becomes its opposite that can
00:45:24.640
become innovating and a source of frustration, not only for the analytic philosophers who are demanding
00:45:31.920
more consistency, but even for people who are struggling to answer these questions like,
00:45:37.760
you were doing about, why does motherhood have to be condemned in a blanket way? Can't there be
00:45:43.520
cases in which the waiter can play his role to the best of his abilities while he's on duty and
00:45:51.920
then be someone else when he's not in so forth? Well, okay, boy, Robert, I got a bunch of things to say
00:45:57.360
to that. One, first of all, is, you know, I think part of our unease with this
00:46:03.440
Kantian and Hegelian background in both Bovar and Sarte is that they both kind of
00:46:08.080
rail against Kant and Hegel as being insufficient and not enough and, you know, Sarte says he's
00:46:14.720
not a Kantian, he's got all these problems with Kant, and he just sounds like a total Kantian.
00:46:19.360
And this, this lecture existentialism is a humanism which you and I have talked about before
00:46:25.440
is just wallowing in kind of pretty easy pop Kantian ethics, which is another wrong with Kantian ethics,
00:46:34.000
right? But if you're a Kantian, then just say you're a Kantian and be done with it. So,
00:46:37.120
so part of it is their resistance to just say, hey, by the way, we agree with Kant on this one.
00:46:42.320
And I think Bovar is a little more honest here than Sarte. I think she's more willing to say
00:46:48.480
Kant's got something to offer us. So I think she's a little less
00:46:54.000
dissimulating on this front about her debts to both Kant and to Hegel. So anything more to say
00:47:01.200
than that, I mean, I kind of want to say back to Green that although I agree the kind of the
00:47:05.920
spiciousness of the, anytime someone takes something further than the giving you something,
00:47:10.720
I see that and there are parts of that book that I think aren't beautifully written or I guess
00:47:17.280
not rigorously written. And in fact, Bovar herself didn't think much of this book, right? She,
00:47:21.760
she kind of poo-pooze it as being not as good as it should have been and, you know, not her best writing.
00:47:27.760
What the ethics of him. Yeah. And I've always been sad about that because I see the book as really powerful.
00:47:33.440
And let me tell you what I suspect, which is that the real power of Sarte and existentialism,
00:47:40.720
Bovarian and existentialism, and these, was a tragic view of human relations,
00:47:46.400
based on this idea that there's going to be this inevitable conflict of reification, who can
00:47:52.400
reify the other, you know, and who is going to survive that encounter. And that this is existentialism
00:48:00.880
when it's being truly honest with itself and it's not, there's no subterfuge of bad faith.
00:48:06.480
But that when Sast and Bovar post-war, immediate post-war, they're faced with a situation in France
00:48:15.200
where Marxism was the hegemonic ideology of the time. And if you were, if you could not
00:48:23.040
somehow conjugate your existentialism with Marxism, you were going to be cast out.
00:48:28.240
You were going to be relegated to an insignificant margin of the, of the intellectual times.
00:48:39.520
And all these kind of specious attempts to make arguments by whereby human solidarity
00:48:46.960
has to become the foundation for decisions rather than human conflict. I think is an act of
00:48:51.760
intellectual bad faith in order to make existentialism palatable to the Marxists.
00:48:57.520
That's what I suspect. Well, I think, I think you're right. Historically, you're without a doubt
00:49:03.440
right, Robert. I think that both Bovar and Sarte felt the pressure, particularly from the Marxists.
00:49:08.720
But I think we, we as existentialists should feel that same pressure, not from the Marxists,
00:49:14.640
but just simply from the position of shouldn't there be such a thing as ethics? Shouldn't we be
00:49:20.160
able to say that some kinds of uses of freedom are better than others? I think we, if we don't know
00:49:27.920
how to ground that in philosophical thinking, then that's a challenge for us.
00:49:33.680
But it's just a case, Jeremy, that Sarte says there are no criteria or no norms for choosing one thing
00:49:40.960
over the other. He gives these great examples in the essay that in the lecture that you
00:49:45.680
existentialism as human doesn't mean speaks about the young man who chooses either to stay
00:49:50.320
with his mother or go and join the resistance. And he, Sarte says, I can't tell you what to do.
00:49:57.680
It's in the choosing that you will have affirmed your commitment. So if you're going to be truly
00:50:05.040
existentially honest, you say that I cannot as existentialism cannot provide ethical norms for choice.
00:50:11.920
Okay, good. So let me, let me try this on you, Robert. If then the choosing is what constitutes
00:50:20.640
the human meaning, right? It's choice itself, then what allows for choice? What is the precondition for choice?
00:50:29.200
Well, it's this human fact about us that we are freedom, we are transcendence. So that is a
00:50:35.040
is a precondition for all of the different kinds of choices we should make. And in some ways,
00:50:40.400
that precondition is a moral ground. It permits choice. And so if there is some kind of
00:50:48.400
aspect of our being, which allows for that, basically ethical creation, creating our own ethics,
00:50:56.080
then that precondition, that prerequisite, is itself an overriding moral ground, freedom itself.
00:51:04.400
So freedom is not only a fact about ourselves, but it is a normative force. We should choose
00:51:11.600
choice making. It is better to choose in the name of freedom because freedom itself governs and allows
00:51:20.080
choice to it. But you said it yourself earlier, I am free to choose to become a mother. And if I choose
00:51:28.880
it in full cognizance of this unconditional freedom and responsibility that I'm thrown into,
00:51:38.000
then it's just as authentic a decision as the person who decides that motherhood is not for her.
00:51:43.680
Great. And here I think this is again, you're calling this intellectual bad faith on
00:51:49.200
bovar and sartz part. And I have to agree with you, particularly with the word of authenticity.
00:51:54.320
So they want authenticity to be kind of a badge of courage, a moral virtue in some ways.
00:52:01.040
Yeah, they want it to be on the right side of history. And I think authenticity can go along with
00:52:07.600
all kinds of choices that we might call from even from an existentialist perspective on ethical.
00:52:14.080
I think especially from an existentialist perspective, all sorts of very dubious choices
00:52:20.160
can be perfectly authentic. This is what is scary about existentialism. This is what can be the cause
00:52:27.120
for a wholesale repudiation of it, precisely the fact that if it's internally consistent with
00:52:33.360
its own premises, it cannot presume to be a normative ethical or it has to find
00:52:40.960
that normative grounding in its existence itself. So it can't look elsewhere.
00:52:48.960
So that's the crucial part is that it can't look elsewhere for normative grounding.
00:52:54.160
And this is the problem with all these as sensuous. We have this problem in high-degree,
00:52:57.360
we have it with Nietzsche, all these people we worry like now, how are we all going to
00:53:01.840
decide when to cross the street together? So this is a built-in problem with existentialism.
00:53:08.720
Again, I think both of our offers us the most clarity about how to meet this problem. And here I
00:53:15.520
think she is the closest to saying you can be authentic and evil. So you can make choices which are
00:53:23.440
in full cognizance of your freedom, but steam roll the freedoms of others and there is an existentialist
00:53:31.200
claim to call that evil. Well, let's say that existentialism and evil can coexist.
00:53:40.000
Let's talk about the authenticity of the behavior of the two protagonists in question,
00:53:50.640
no? Yes. Because you know better than I do that they had relations with others,
00:53:58.560
and especially younger women where Beauvoir was seducing her students, sometimes the 16-year-old,
00:54:07.680
17-year-old getting these young women into a network passing them on to Jean-Paul Sast and
00:54:16.880
we don't have to rehearse all the sorted details, but these are facts that have come out
00:54:23.520
with documentation that are even much more revealing since the death of Simone de Vaudevac. Oh, yes.
00:54:28.880
But actually you say, well, were they either being in bad faith when they were espousing
00:54:37.040
all this moral righteousness of existential authenticity as a criterion or were they being
00:54:46.720
existentially authentic and yet opting for things that you and I might consider if not evil, then
00:54:52.240
ethically very dubious. Great, Robert. I mean, this is a tough subject for me because I admire these two.
00:55:01.600
And you and I were talking about this the other day and I was saying, well, you look at any
00:55:09.120
figure in history and the more you learn about them, the worse they look and so what you choose
00:55:14.160
not to look closely or you accept that human beings are imperfect, morally imperfect,
00:55:20.560
and you stop me short and I just want to call that out that for some reason it seems worse with
00:55:26.080
these two, that they're moral failings or they're failings as individuals. They're personal life,
00:55:30.400
the choices they made seem somehow more their hypocrisy, seem more urgent and more
00:55:39.280
important for us to dwell on than with other people, that somehow worse.
00:55:43.920
Well, yeah, because you we can assume that there's exploitation there in full.
00:55:49.920
Now, in my more favorable moments, I say that the authenticity of Satsnab of what on this issue
00:56:00.240
was to go out there and publicly campaign for the abolition of the age of consent. Okay,
00:56:07.520
great. If you will go out there and say that the age of consent when it comes to sex
00:56:13.200
is doesn't make sense that it's denying the agency of even young teenage girls and boys,
00:56:22.560
then you could say that the seductions of her students age 16 or 17 and the Minajatwa
00:56:30.720
was humble Satsnab that I am treating them, I'm speaking in her voice, I am treating these young people
00:56:38.000
as full-fledged human agents capable of choice and for society to condescend and say that you don't
00:56:46.080
have the existential maturity to make decisions for yourself until you reach age 18 is a form of
00:56:53.440
institutionalized bad faith in the society as a whole. That I can agree with because I
00:57:00.160
you know, if you were raised a Catholic like I was there was the age of reason was seven, no,
00:57:06.480
yep, until age seven you were not liable for damnation, eternal damnation because you were
00:57:12.800
only after age seven could you commit a mortal sin because you knew the difference between right
00:57:17.840
and wrong. So that's if you want a age of consent, let's make it seven anyway. In other words,
00:57:22.880
okay, yep, and yeah, so you can go to hell when you're able you can't you're not allowed to have
00:57:27.360
sex. That's right, yeah. That's what that's what they're argument.
00:57:30.880
Yep. And so, okay, so the moment you're referring to Robert is this petition that both
00:57:38.720
Warren Sart signed in 1977 against the age of consent that Michel Foucault was associated with
00:57:45.360
and a younger generation in fact, it was thinking about social power and state control,
00:57:51.440
particularly as a way of persecuting non-normative sexualities. And I think this is a moment where
00:57:59.360
both Warren Sart were and actually all the philosophers that got behind this petition were
00:58:04.960
if not on the wrong side of history, certainly blindsided. I mean, I think they were
00:58:08.720
Foucault in particular is this theorist of power and to ignore the kind of power dynamics that
00:58:14.960
occur between a young person or an older person, right, all that kind of stuff. It all is kind of
00:58:20.640
careful examinations of not just institutionalized power but social power, individual power relations
00:58:26.800
to see that the age of consent or the sexual relations between a young person and an old person
00:58:34.000
is somehow only permeated by institutional power relations instead of interpersonal power relations.
00:58:41.280
I think it's just extremely short-sighted. So I think they made that mistake along with Michel Foucault
00:58:46.480
and many others. I do think that their own choices, and here not in 1977, but in the 60s and the 50s
00:58:54.160
and the 40s, their own personal choices to kind of ensnare people who were bold over by their
00:59:01.760
intellectual brilliance and their cosmopolitan lifestyle and to use them and abuse them and then
00:59:10.640
discard them. I think has nothing to do with this later formulation of age of consent. There, I think
00:59:18.560
that 1977 age of consent is an attempt to become consistent philosophically with lived principles.
00:59:24.960
I think if you go back to this earlier time in their lives when they were most guilty of this kind
00:59:30.080
of ensnarement, there's nothing like that going on at all. It's just completely has nothing to do
00:59:37.520
with seeing the other as a subject with their own legitimacy and authenticity. It's just purely using
00:59:44.720
the most object. I just think there's no way around that. I think to wrap it all up. Yes, we
00:59:52.960
began by saying that the thought of Beuwad is still profoundly relevant to today. Not because
01:00:00.400
we live in a world which is existentialist. If anything, our times are rather steeped in bad faith
01:00:10.080
from all sides and at all ages, and at least I'm speaking for myself now, I'm not speaking for you,
01:00:17.680
but I think that what we need the most is a heavy dose of existentialist realism about
01:00:26.160
our own strong agency when it comes to the things that happen to me, the choices that I make.
01:00:36.960
The subterfuge of thinking that somehow I'm not on the bad side of things that I'm always on the
01:00:43.440
good side of things. Yeah, and so for me, I do agree with you, Robert, I think that
01:00:51.680
And this is to me why Beuwad is so compelling, is that Beuwad, she's an existentialist. So at the core,
01:00:57.520
she believes in human freedom, individual choices that we are responsible for how we respond to
01:01:03.840
the situation we're in. And I don't think she ever let's go of that. And yet, particularly in the
01:01:09.440
second sex, she is able to use that analysis of human freedom to show us a world which seems like
01:01:19.760
allows certain groups lived out freedoms that are different than others. So it gives us a way to
01:01:25.920
analyze social forces, social pressures, to identify victims without taking away their agency and
01:01:32.720
their choice. So this is our problem, right? And in our contemporary world, we're constantly wanting
01:01:38.240
to honor and empower individuals for their autonomy and freedom. But we also want to recognize
01:01:44.640
that there are the victim of social pressures and it's a zero-sum game, right? The more agency we give
01:01:50.080
them, the more we turn them into responsible for their fate and the more we acknowledge that they
01:01:57.680
have been the recipients of crimes at their victims, the more we turn them into an object. So
01:02:01.840
there's no way to win. And Beuwad's project in the second sex is to say that we have to have it
01:02:06.800
both ways, that we can be once victims, legitimately objectively describe that there's such a
01:02:12.800
thing as oppression out there. And yet that doesn't do you? That's not the whole story. We're still,
01:02:18.000
we still have freedoms and in fact we'll never understand that oppression unless we understand
01:02:23.120
that oppression is caused by human freedom. And it's also transcendable. Yep. So to me, her language of
01:02:29.440
bringing those together, not one at the expense of the other, but to see those as both vital
01:02:35.200
components at social description to just understand the world we live in, I find very, very exciting.
01:02:41.680
Well said, we've been speaking with Jeremy Sable here on entitled opinions. Thanks for joining us,
01:02:47.120
Jeremy. Thanks for having me. It was a long wait, but well worth it. And all you listeners out there,
01:02:54.480
or title opinions, we'll be looking forward to having you next time. Take care. Bye bye.
01:03:00.320
[Music]
01:03:23.520
[Music]
01:03:52.320
[Music]
01:04:13.440
[Music]
01:04:23.440
[Music]
01:04:33.440
[Music]
01:04:43.440
[Music]
01:05:07.440
[Music]
01:05:17.440
[Music]
01:05:27.440
[Music]
01:05:47.440
[Music]
01:06:07.440
[Music]
01:06:31.440
[Music]
01:06:55.440
[Music]
01:07:05.440
[Music]
01:07:15.440
[Music]
01:07:25.440
[Music]
01:07:35.440
[Music]
01:07:45.440
[Music]
01:07:55.440
[Music]
01:08:05.440
[Music]
01:08:25.440
[Music]
01:08:29.440
[BLANK_AUDIO]